Knowledge

Infinite regress

Source 📝

513:
other than by demonstration, maintain that an infinite regress is involved, on the ground that if behind the prior stands no primary, we could not know the posterior through the prior (wherein they are right, for one cannot traverse an infinite series): if on the other hand – they say – the series terminates and there are primary premises, yet these are unknowable because incapable of demonstration, which according to them is the only form of knowledge. And since thus one cannot know the primary premises, knowledge of the conclusions which follow from them is not pure scientific knowledge nor properly knowing at all, but rests on the mere supposition that the premises are true. The other party agrees with them as regards knowing, holding that it is only possible by demonstration, but they see no difficulty in holding that all truths are demonstrated, on the ground that demonstration may be circular and reciprocal. Our own doctrine is that not all knowledge is demonstrative: on the contrary, knowledge of the immediate premises is independent of demonstration. (The necessity of this is obvious; for since we must know the prior premises from which the demonstration is drawn, and since the regress must end in immediate truths, those truths must be indemonstrable.) Such, then, is our doctrine, and in addition, we maintain that besides scientific knowledge there is its original source which enables us to recognize the definitions.
455:. It posits that there is a first element in the series from which all the other elements arise but which is not itself explained this way. So from any given position, the series can be traced back to elements on the most fundamental level, which the recursive principle fails to explain. This way an infinite regress is avoided. This position is well-known from its applications in the field of epistemology. Foundationalist theories of epistemic justification state that besides inferentially justified beliefs, which depend for their justification on other beliefs, there are also non-inferentially justified beliefs. The non-inferentially justified beliefs constitute the foundation on which the superstructure consisting of all the inferentially justified beliefs rests. Acquaintance theories, for example, explain the justification of non-inferential beliefs through acquaintance with the objects of the belief. On such a view, an agent is inferentially justified to believe that it will rain tomorrow based on the belief that the weather forecast told so. They are non-inferentially justified in believing that they are in pain because they are directly acquainted with the pain. So a different type of explanation (acquaintance) is used for the foundational elements. 488:, mostly found in the field of epistemology, is another way to avoid infinite regresses. It is based on a holistic explanation that usually sees the entities in question not as a linear series but as an interconnected network. For example, coherentist theories of epistemic justification hold that beliefs are justified because of the way they hang together: they cohere well with each other. This view can be expressed by stating that justification is primarily a property of the system of beliefs as a whole. The justification of a single belief is derivative in the sense that it depends on the fact that this belief belongs to a coherent whole. 278:. Other types occur when the infinite regress is responsible for the theory in question being implausible or for its failure to solve the problem it was formulated to solve. The vice of an infinite regress can be local if it causes problems only for certain theories when combined with other assumptions, or global otherwise. For example, an otherwise virtuous regress is locally vicious for a theory that posits a finite domain. In some cases, an infinite regress is not itself the source of the problem but merely indicates a different underlying problem. 295:
has been argued that only certain types of infinities are problematic in this way, like infinite intensive magnitudes (e.g. infinite energy densities). But other types of infinities, like infinite cardinality (e.g. infinitely many causes) or infinite extensive magnitude (e.g. the duration of the universe's history) are unproblematic from the point of view of metaphysical impossibility. While there may be some instances of viciousness due to metaphysical impossibility, most vicious regresses are problematic because of other reasons.
398:. The problem is that to transfer something, it first must be possessed, so the possession is presumed rather than explained. For example, in trying to explain why one's neighbor has the property of being the owner of a bag of sugar, it is revealed that this bag was first in someone else's possession before it was transferred to the neighbor and that the same is true for this and every other previous owner. This explanation is unsatisfying since ownership is presupposed at every step. In non-transmissive explanations, however, 27: 1384: 218:
triggering condition) and (2) that this infinite regress is vicious (e.g. by showing that it is implausible given the limitations of the human mind). In this example, the argument has a negative form since it only denies that another theory is true. But it can also be used in a positive form to support a theory by showing that its alternative involves a vicious regress. This is how the
342:. From the perspective of a mythological world view, for example, one way to explain why the earth seems to be at rest instead of falling down is to hold that it rests on the back of a giant turtle. In order to explain why the turtle itself is not in free fall, another even bigger turtle is posited and so on, resulting in a world that is 304:
possible. It only denies that it is actual. For example, it seems implausible due to the limitations of the human mind that there are justified beliefs if this entails that the agent needs to have an infinite amount of them. But this is not metaphysically impossible, e.g. if it is assumed that the infinite number of beliefs are only
313:, which posits that we should avoid ontological extravagance by not multiplying entities without necessity. Considerations of parsimony are complicated by the distinction between quantitative and qualitative parsimony: concerning how many entities are posited in contrast to how many kinds of entities are posited. For example, the 512:
Some hold that owing to the necessity of knowing the primary premises, there is no scientific knowledge. Others think there is, but that all truths are demonstrable. Neither doctrine is either true or a necessary deduction from the premises. The first school, assuming that there is no way of knowing
152:
stands for a property in the widest sense. In the epistemic regress, for example, a belief is justified because it is based on another belief that is justified. But this other belief is itself in need of one more justified belief for itself to be justified and so on. Or in the cosmological argument,
294:
are impossible, thereby directly leading to a contradiction. This anti-infinitists position is opposed to infinity in general, not just specifically to infinite regresses. But it is open to defenders of the theory in question to deny this outright prohibition on actual infinities. For example, it
362:
explanation, on the other hand, tries to explain why there are any things with this property at all. So as a local explanation, the regress in the turtle theory is benign: it succeeds in explaining why the earth is not falling. But as a global explanation, it fails because it has to assume rather
333:
Another form of viciousness applies not to the infinite regress by itself but to it in relation to the explanatory goals of a theory. Theories are often formulated with the goal of solving a specific problem, e.g. of answering the question why a certain type of entity exists. One way how such an
303:
A more common form of viciousness arises from the implausibility of the infinite regress in question. This category often applies to theories about human actions, states or capacities. This argument is weaker than the argument from impossibility since it allows that the regress in question is
217:
in epistemology holds that a belief is only justified if it is based on another belief that is justified. An opponent of this theory could use an infinite regress argument by demonstrating (1) that this theory leads to an infinite regress (e.g. by pointing out the recursive principle and the
71:
Traditionally, it was often assumed without much argument that each infinite regress is vicious but this assumption has been put into question in contemporary philosophy. While some philosophers have explicitly defended theories with infinite regresses, the more common strategy has been to
470:
is the thesis that these dependence relations do not form an infinite regress: that there is a most fundamental level that grounds the existence of the entities from all other levels. This is sometimes expressed by stating that the grounding-relation responsible for this hierarchy is
213:. The mere existence of an infinite regress by itself is not a proof for anything. So in addition to connecting the theory to a recursive principle paired with a triggering condition, the argument has to show in which way the resulting regress is vicious. For example, one form of 250:. Traditionally, it was often assumed without much argument that each infinite regress is vicious but this assumption has been put into question in contemporary philosophy. In most cases, it is not self-evident whether an infinite regress is vicious or not. The 422:
point of view, for example, justification or evidence can be defined in terms of one belief raising the probability that another belief is true. The former belief may also be justified but this is not relevant for explaining why the latter belief is justified.
346:. Despite its shortcomings in clashing with modern physics and due to its ontological extravagance, this theory seems to be metaphysically possible assuming that space is infinite. One way to assess the viciousness of this regress is to distinguish between 208:
is an argument against a theory based on the fact that this theory leads to an infinite regress. For such an argument to be successful, it has to demonstrate not just that the theory in question entails an infinite regress but also that this regress is
254:
constitutes an example of an infinite regress that is not vicious: if the proposition "P" is true, then the proposition that "It is true that P" is also true and so on. Infinite regresses pose a problem mostly if the regress concerns concrete objects.
153:
an event occurred because it was caused by another event that occurred before it, which was itself caused by a previous event, and so on. This principle by itself is not sufficient: it does not lead to a regress if there is no
107:
is an infinite series of entities governed by a recursive principle that determines how each entity in the series depends on or is produced by its predecessor. This principle can often be expressed in the following form:
308:
while the limitation only applies to the number of beliefs one is actually thinking about at one moment. Another reason for the implausibility of theories involving an infinite regress is due to the principle known as
49:, for example, a belief is justified because it is based on another belief that is justified. But this other belief is itself in need of one more justified belief for itself to be justified and so on. An 466:. One position in this debate claims that some entities exist on a more fundamental level than other entities and that the latter entities depend on or are grounded in the former entities. 435:, on the other hand, embrace the regress but deny that it is vicious. Another response is to modify the theory in order to avoid the regress. This can be achieved in the form of 431:
Philosophers have responded to infinite regress arguments in various ways. The criticized theory can be defended, for example, by denying that an infinite regress is involved.
68:. Other forms occur when the infinite regress is responsible for the theory in question being implausible or for its failure to solve the problem it was formulated to solve. 358:
explanation is only interested in explaining why one thing has a certain property through reference to another thing without trying to explain this other thing as well. A
201:
and so on. Once the regress has started, there is no way of stopping it since a new entity has to be introduced at each step in order to make the previous step possible.
366:
It has been argued that infinite regresses can be benign under certain circumstances despite aiming at global explanation. This line of thought rests on the idea of the
259:, on the other hand, are often considered to be unproblematic in this respect. For example, the truth-regress leads to an infinite number of true propositions or the 78:, which posits that there is a first element in the series from which all the other elements arise but which is not itself explained this way. Another way is 545:
is implausible because it produces an infinite regress of "inner observers" when trying to explain how mental states are able to influence physical states.
56:
For such an argument to be successful, it must demonstrate not just that the theory in question entails an infinite regress but also that this regress is
84:, which is based on a holistic explanation that usually sees the entities in question not as a linear series but as an interconnected network. 1203:"Infinite Regress Arguments > Metaphysical Foundationalism and the Well-Foundedness of Grounding (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)" 418:
but this is just seen as a contingent fact. This line of thought has been used to argue that the epistemic regress is not vicious. From a
334:
attempt can fail is if the answer to the question already assumes in disguised form what it was supposed to explain. This is akin to the
222:
for the existence of God works: it claims that positing God's existence is necessary in order to avoid an infinite regress of causes.
321:
parsimony by positing that there is one first cause instead of allowing an infinite chain of events. But it does so by decreasing
625: 363:
than explain at each step that there is another thing that is not falling. It does not explain why nothing at all is falling.
1292: 290:
are the most serious cases of viciousness. The easiest way to arrive at this result is by accepting the assumption that
635: 508:
argued that knowing does not necessitate an infinite regress because some knowledge does not depend on demonstration:
1388: 1339: 20: 1403: 60:. There are different ways in which a regress can be vicious. The most serious form of viciousness involves a 560: 555: 463: 270:
There are different ways how a regress can be vicious. The most serious type of viciousness involves a
1202: 87:
Infinite regress arguments have been made in various areas of philosophy. Famous examples include the
42:
principle that determines how each entity in the series depends on or is produced by its predecessor.
1314: 343: 53:
is an argument against a theory based on the fact that this theory leads to an infinite regress.
1272: 610: 1329: 580: 473: 419: 314: 219: 88: 1364: 1057: 1334:. SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy. State University of New York Press. p. 83. 570: 339: 305: 92: 1128: 72:
reformulate the theory in question in a way that avoids the regress. One such strategy is
8: 640: 605: 520: 161:. This is why an additional triggering condition has to be fulfilled: there has to be an 1408: 1302: 1228: 1104: 1004: 962: 759: 717: 630: 575: 538: 1345: 1335: 1288: 1108: 966: 542: 310: 291: 177:. According to the recursive principle, this is only possible if there is a distinct 46: 1008: 1280: 1096: 1038: 996: 954: 799: 751: 620: 600: 565: 489: 335: 256: 267:. But these regresses are usually not held against the theories that entail them. 1284: 1000: 264: 74: 1172: 1042: 958: 803: 1397: 585: 271: 214: 61: 981: 534: 260: 1100: 590: 459: 169:
for the regress to get started. So the regress starts with the fact that
80: 1026: 763: 1255: 1157:
The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality
1155: 26: 853: 615: 505: 39: 1084: 942: 852:
Huemer, Michael (2016). "13. Assessing Infinite Regress Arguments".
787: 755: 739: 887: 886:
Maurin, Anna-Sofia (2007). "Infinite Regress - Virtue or Vice?".
595: 1349: 909: 1383: 626:
The Unreality of Time § The contradiction of the A-series
234:
to be successful, it has to show that the involved regress is
426: 492:
is a well-known contemporary defender of this position.
1129:"Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification" 1196: 1194: 370:
involved in the vicious cases: it is explained that
325:parsimony: it posits God as a new type of entity. 1229:"Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification" 1191: 1395: 724:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 38:is an infinite series of entities governed by a 1235:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1179:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1135:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1064:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University 1160:. Oxford University Press. pp. 13, 29–31. 556:Action (philosophy) § Basic and non-basic 317:for the existence of God promises to increase 1126: 1170: 892:. Department of Philosophy, Lund University. 185:. But in order to account for the fact that 451:Traditionally, the most common response is 1279:. Springer Netherlands. pp. 125–133. 711: 709: 707: 705: 703: 701: 699: 697: 695: 693: 691: 689: 687: 685: 683: 681: 679: 677: 1362: 1277:The Current State of the Coherence Theory 936: 934: 932: 930: 847: 845: 843: 841: 839: 837: 835: 833: 675: 673: 671: 669: 667: 665: 663: 661: 659: 657: 1122: 1120: 1118: 1082: 982:"What Not to Multiply Without Necessity" 979: 881: 879: 877: 875: 873: 871: 869: 867: 865: 831: 829: 827: 825: 823: 821: 819: 817: 815: 813: 458:Another example comes from the field of 263:entail the existence of infinitely many 25: 1270: 1253: 1233:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1177:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1133:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1062:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1055: 940: 903: 901: 899: 733: 731: 722:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 715: 427:Responses to infinite regress arguments 1396: 1226: 1127:Hasan, Ali; Fumerton, Richard (2018). 1020: 1018: 927: 885: 851: 654: 1327: 1171:Bliss, Ricki; Trogdon, Kelly (2016). 1115: 862: 810: 781: 779: 777: 775: 773: 737: 529: 328: 1257:The Structure of Empirical Knowledge 1153: 1024: 896: 740:"Vicious Infinite Regress Arguments" 728: 1331:Analysis & Science in Aristotle 1200: 1015: 914:Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 785: 30:An illustration of infinite regress 13: 989:Australasian Journal of Philosophy 770: 636:What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 446: 14: 1420: 1377: 907: 298: 21:Infinite regress (disambiguation) 1382: 1083:Hájek, Alan; Lin, Hanti (2017). 286:Infinite regresses that involve 281: 1356: 1321: 1264: 1247: 1220: 1164: 1147: 1085:"A Tale of Two Epistemologies?" 1076: 1049: 858:. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. 566:Axiology § Intrinsic value 973: 480: 306:non-occurrent or dispositional 225: 1: 647: 561:Antecedent-contained deletion 390:was somehow transmitted from 98: 1369:. B.H. Blackwell. p. 7. 1328:Byrne, Patrick Hugh (1997). 1285:10.1007/978-94-009-2360-7_11 1001:10.1080/00048402.2014.992447 943:"Infinite Regress Arguments" 941:Wieland, Jan Willem (2013). 910:"Infinitism in Epistemology" 788:"Infinite Regress Arguments" 786:Day, Timothy Joseph (1987). 718:"Infinite Regress Arguments" 500: 468:Metaphysical foundationalism 7: 1260:. Harvard University Press. 1043:10.1111/1468-0068.36.s16.11 980:Schaffer, Jonathan (2015). 548: 495: 10: 1425: 1254:BonJour, Laurence (1985). 744:Philosophical Perspectives 462:concerning the problem of 288:metaphysical impossibility 276:metaphysical impossibility 148:stands for a relation and 66:metaphysical impossibility 18: 1271:Goldman, Alan H. (1989). 1056:Talbott, William (2016). 1027:"The Source Of Necessity" 959:10.1007/s12136-012-0165-1 804:10.1080/05568648709506273 232:infinite regress argument 206:infinite regress argument 51:infinite regress argument 1173:"Metaphysical Grounding" 402:is still the reason for 344:turtles all the way down 1404:Philosophical arguments 1273:"BonJour's Coherentism" 1058:"Bayesian Epistemology" 738:Clark, Romane (1988). 716:Cameron, Ross (2018). 527: 31: 1391:at Wikimedia Commons 1227:Olsson, Erik (2017). 1154:Audi, Robert (2001). 1101:10.11612/resphil.1540 581:Cosmological argument 510: 464:ontological hierarchy 315:cosmological argument 220:cosmological argument 193:, we need to posit a 89:cosmological argument 29: 16:Philosophical problem 855:Approaching Infinity 792:Philosophical Papers 611:Münchhausen trilemma 340:begging the question 19:For other uses, see 1366:Posterior Analytics 606:Homunculus argument 521:Posterior Analytics 144:stand for objects, 1363:Aristotle (1901). 1207:plato.stanford.edu 1025:Hale, Bob (2002). 631:Third man argument 576:Chicken or the egg 539:philosophy of mind 530:Philosophy of mind 329:Failure to explain 242:regress is called 32: 1387:Media related to 1294:978-94-010-7563-3 571:Bradley's regress 543:mind-body dualism 292:actual infinities 93:Bradley's regress 47:epistemic regress 1416: 1389:Infinite regress 1386: 1371: 1370: 1360: 1354: 1353: 1325: 1319: 1318: 1312: 1308: 1306: 1298: 1268: 1262: 1261: 1251: 1245: 1244: 1242: 1240: 1224: 1218: 1217: 1215: 1213: 1198: 1189: 1188: 1186: 1184: 1168: 1162: 1161: 1151: 1145: 1144: 1142: 1140: 1124: 1113: 1112: 1089:Res Philosophica 1080: 1074: 1073: 1071: 1069: 1053: 1047: 1046: 1037:(s16): 299–319. 1022: 1013: 1012: 986: 977: 971: 970: 938: 925: 924: 922: 920: 908:Klein, Peter D. 905: 894: 893: 889:Hommage À Wlodek 883: 860: 859: 849: 808: 807: 783: 768: 767: 735: 726: 725: 713: 641:Zeno's paradoxes 621:Regress argument 601:Gunk (mereology) 525: 490:Laurence BonJour 354:explanations. A 336:informal fallacy 257:Abstract objects 105:infinite regress 36:infinite regress 1424: 1423: 1419: 1418: 1417: 1415: 1414: 1413: 1394: 1393: 1380: 1375: 1374: 1361: 1357: 1342: 1326: 1322: 1310: 1309: 1300: 1299: 1295: 1269: 1265: 1252: 1248: 1238: 1236: 1225: 1221: 1211: 1209: 1201:Cameron, Ross. 1199: 1192: 1182: 1180: 1169: 1165: 1152: 1148: 1138: 1136: 1125: 1116: 1081: 1077: 1067: 1065: 1054: 1050: 1023: 1016: 984: 978: 974: 939: 928: 918: 916: 906: 897: 884: 863: 850: 811: 784: 771: 756:10.2307/2214081 736: 729: 714: 655: 650: 645: 551: 532: 526: 517: 503: 498: 483: 453:foundationalism 449: 447:Foundationalism 437:foundationalism 429: 331: 301: 284: 274:in the form of 265:natural numbers 228: 101: 75:foundationalism 64:in the form of 24: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1422: 1412: 1411: 1406: 1379: 1378:External links 1376: 1373: 1372: 1355: 1340: 1320: 1311:|journal= 1293: 1263: 1246: 1219: 1190: 1163: 1146: 1114: 1095:(2): 207–232. 1075: 1048: 1014: 995:(4): 644–664. 972: 947:Acta Analytica 926: 895: 861: 809: 798:(2): 155–164. 769: 727: 652: 651: 649: 646: 644: 643: 638: 633: 628: 623: 618: 613: 608: 603: 598: 593: 588: 583: 578: 573: 568: 563: 558: 552: 550: 547: 537:argues in the 531: 528: 515: 502: 499: 497: 494: 482: 479: 448: 445: 428: 425: 330: 327: 311:Ockham's razor 300: 299:Implausibility 297: 283: 280: 227: 224: 100: 97: 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1421: 1410: 1407: 1405: 1402: 1401: 1399: 1392: 1390: 1385: 1368: 1367: 1359: 1351: 1347: 1343: 1341:9780791433218 1337: 1333: 1332: 1324: 1316: 1304: 1296: 1290: 1286: 1282: 1278: 1274: 1267: 1259: 1258: 1250: 1234: 1230: 1223: 1208: 1204: 1197: 1195: 1178: 1174: 1167: 1159: 1158: 1150: 1134: 1130: 1123: 1121: 1119: 1110: 1106: 1102: 1098: 1094: 1090: 1086: 1079: 1063: 1059: 1052: 1044: 1040: 1036: 1032: 1028: 1021: 1019: 1010: 1006: 1002: 998: 994: 990: 983: 976: 968: 964: 960: 956: 953:(1): 95–109. 952: 948: 944: 937: 935: 933: 931: 915: 911: 904: 902: 900: 891: 890: 882: 880: 878: 876: 874: 872: 870: 868: 866: 857: 856: 848: 846: 844: 842: 840: 838: 836: 834: 832: 830: 828: 826: 824: 822: 820: 818: 816: 814: 805: 801: 797: 793: 789: 782: 780: 778: 776: 774: 765: 761: 757: 753: 749: 745: 741: 734: 732: 723: 719: 712: 710: 708: 706: 704: 702: 700: 698: 696: 694: 692: 690: 688: 686: 684: 682: 680: 678: 676: 674: 672: 670: 668: 666: 664: 662: 660: 658: 653: 642: 639: 637: 634: 632: 629: 627: 624: 622: 619: 617: 614: 612: 609: 607: 604: 602: 599: 597: 594: 592: 589: 587: 586:Droste effect 584: 582: 579: 577: 574: 572: 569: 567: 564: 562: 559: 557: 554: 553: 546: 544: 540: 536: 523: 522: 514: 509: 507: 493: 491: 487: 478: 476: 475: 469: 465: 461: 456: 454: 444: 442: 438: 434: 424: 421: 417: 413: 409: 405: 401: 397: 393: 389: 385: 381: 377: 373: 369: 364: 361: 357: 353: 349: 345: 341: 337: 326: 324: 320: 316: 312: 307: 296: 293: 289: 282:Impossibility 279: 277: 273: 272:contradiction 268: 266: 262: 258: 253: 252:truth regress 249: 245: 241: 237: 233: 223: 221: 216: 215:evidentialism 212: 207: 202: 200: 196: 192: 188: 184: 181:that is also 180: 176: 172: 168: 164: 160: 156: 151: 147: 143: 139: 135: 131: 127: 123: 119: 115: 111: 106: 96: 94: 90: 85: 83: 82: 77: 76: 69: 67: 63: 62:contradiction 59: 54: 52: 48: 43: 41: 37: 28: 22: 1381: 1365: 1358: 1330: 1323: 1276: 1266: 1256: 1249: 1237:. Retrieved 1232: 1222: 1210:. Retrieved 1206: 1181:. Retrieved 1176: 1166: 1156: 1149: 1137:. Retrieved 1132: 1092: 1088: 1078: 1066:. Retrieved 1061: 1051: 1034: 1030: 992: 988: 975: 950: 946: 917:. Retrieved 913: 888: 854: 795: 791: 747: 743: 721: 535:Gilbert Ryle 533: 519: 511: 504: 485: 484: 474:well-founded 472: 467: 457: 452: 450: 440: 436: 432: 430: 415: 411: 407: 403: 399: 395: 391: 387: 383: 379: 375: 371: 368:transmission 367: 365: 359: 355: 351: 347: 332: 322: 319:quantitative 318: 302: 287: 285: 275: 269: 261:Peano axioms 251: 247: 243: 239: 235: 231: 229: 210: 205: 203: 198: 194: 190: 186: 182: 178: 174: 170: 166: 162: 158: 154: 149: 145: 141: 137: 133: 129: 125: 121: 117: 113: 109: 104: 102: 86: 79: 73: 70: 65: 57: 55: 50: 44: 35: 33: 750:: 369–380. 591:First cause 524:I.3 72b1–15 518:Aristotle, 486:Coherentism 481:Coherentism 460:metaphysics 441:coherentism 433:Infinitists 386:where this 323:qualitative 240:non-vicious 226:Viciousness 81:coherentism 1398:Categories 648:References 120:stands in 99:Definition 1409:Recursion 1313:ignored ( 1303:cite book 1109:160029122 967:170181468 616:Recursion 506:Aristotle 501:Aristotle 40:recursive 1350:96037783 1212:10 March 1183:10 March 1009:16923735 919:10 March 549:See also 516:—  496:Examples 420:Bayesian 414:is also 378:because 244:virtuous 197:that is 165:that is 157:that is 116:because 1239:9 March 1139:9 March 1068:6 March 764:2214081 596:Fractal 236:vicious 230:For an 211:vicious 58:vicious 45:In the 1348:  1338:  1291:  1107:  1007:  965:  762:  439:or of 406:being 360:global 352:global 248:benign 1105:S2CID 1005:S2CID 985:(PDF) 963:S2CID 760:JSTOR 541:that 356:local 348:local 1346:LCCN 1336:ISBN 1315:help 1289:ISBN 1241:2021 1214:2021 1185:2021 1141:2021 1070:2021 1031:Noûs 921:2021 410:and 350:and 238:. A 140:and 128:and 91:and 1281:doi 1097:doi 1039:doi 997:doi 955:doi 800:doi 752:doi 394:to 382:is 374:is 338:of 246:or 204:An 189:is 173:is 132:is 124:to 112:is 103:An 34:An 1400:: 1344:. 1307:: 1305:}} 1301:{{ 1287:. 1275:. 1231:. 1205:. 1193:^ 1175:. 1131:. 1117:^ 1103:. 1093:94 1091:. 1087:. 1060:. 1035:36 1033:. 1029:. 1017:^ 1003:. 993:93 991:. 987:. 961:. 951:28 949:. 945:. 929:^ 912:. 898:^ 864:^ 812:^ 796:16 794:. 790:. 772:^ 758:. 746:. 742:. 730:^ 720:. 656:^ 477:. 443:. 136:. 95:. 1352:. 1317:) 1297:. 1283:: 1243:. 1216:. 1187:. 1143:. 1111:. 1099:: 1072:. 1045:. 1041:: 1011:. 999:: 969:. 957:: 923:. 806:. 802:: 766:. 754:: 748:2 416:F 412:Y 408:F 404:X 400:Y 396:X 392:Y 388:F 384:F 380:Y 376:F 372:X 199:F 195:Z 191:F 187:Y 183:F 179:Y 175:F 171:X 167:F 163:X 159:F 155:X 150:F 146:R 142:Y 138:X 134:F 130:Y 126:Y 122:R 118:X 114:F 110:X 23:.

Index

Infinite regress (disambiguation)

recursive
epistemic regress
contradiction
foundationalism
coherentism
cosmological argument
Bradley's regress
evidentialism
cosmological argument
Abstract objects
Peano axioms
natural numbers
contradiction
actual infinities
non-occurrent or dispositional
Ockham's razor
cosmological argument
informal fallacy
begging the question
turtles all the way down
Bayesian
metaphysics
ontological hierarchy
well-founded
Laurence BonJour
Aristotle
Posterior Analytics
Gilbert Ryle

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.