Knowledge

Average and total utilitarianism

Source đź“ť

423: 504:
Creating a less-than-average life would become an immoral act. Furthermore, in a world where everyone was experiencing very bad lives that were not worth living, adding more people whose lives were also not worth living, but were less unpleasant than the lives of those who already existed, would raise the average, and appear to be a moral duty.
519:) may temper the aforementioned undesirable conclusions. That is, actually practicing a rule that we must "kill anyone who is less happy than average" would almost certainly cause suffering in the long run. Alternatively, average utilitarianism may be bolstered by a "life worth living" threshold. This threshold would be placed very low ( 474:(or "happiness points") is judged as preferable to a group of 1,000 people with 99 hedons each. More counter intuitively still, average utilitarianism evaluates the existence of a single person with 100 hedons more favorably than an outcome in which a million people have an average utility of 99 hedons. 457:
To survive the mere addition paradox with a consistent model of total utilitarianism, total utilitarians have two choices. They may either assert that higher utility living is on a completely different scale from, and thus incomparable to, the bottom levels of utility, or deny that there is anything
481:
are still relevant here: Even though "Parfit's repugnant conclusion" (mentioned above) is avoided by average utilitarianism, some generally repugnant conclusions may still obtain. For instance, if there are two completely isolated societies, one a 100-hedon society and the other a 99-hedon society,
503:
Parfit himself provided another similar criticism. Average utilitarianism seems to reject what Parfit calls "mere addition": the addition or creation of new lives that, although they may not be as happy as the average (and thus bring down the average), may still be intuitively well worth living.
527:
to consider their execution. This obtains the intuition that a generally lower 'average utility' is to be endured provided there are no individuals who would be "better off dead". This would also allow average utilitarianism to acknowledge the general human preference for life.
438:
Total utilitarianism is a method of applying utilitarianism to a group to work out what the best set of outcomes would be. It assumes that the target utility is the maximum utility across the population based on adding all the separate utilities of each individual together.
458:
wrong with the repugnant conclusion. (Although, Sikora argues that we may already be living within this minimal state. Particularly as quality of life measurements are generally relative and we cannot know how we would appear to a society with very high quality of life.)
430:
principles, population ought to be encouraged to increase, is not that at which average happiness is the greatest possible...but that at which the product formed by multiplying the number of persons living into the amount of average happiness reaches its maximum." ~
490:
Utilitarian theory is embarrassed by the possibility of utility monsters who get enormously greater sums of utility from any sacrifice of others than these others lose ... the theory seems to require that we all be sacrificed in the monster's maw.
549:(not total happiness) and 'good' (which he takes as meaning per capita happiness), although the same principle of course applies to average and total happiness. His conclusion "we want the maximum good per person" is taken as being self-evident. 482:
then strict average utilitarianism seems to support killing off the 99-hedon society (this violent action would increase the average utility in this scenario). This criticism is also exemplified by Nozick's
486:, a hypothetical being with a greater ability to gain utility from resources, who takes all those resources from people in a fashion that is seen as completely immoral. Nozick writes: 446:", which argues that a likely outcome of following total utilitarianism is a future where there is a large number of people with very low utility values. 642: 414:, a philosophical field that deals with problems arising when our actions affect the number or identity of individuals born in the future. 499:
Maximizing the average utility allows a person to kill everyone else if that would make him ecstatic, and so happier than average.
370: 545:'s goal of "the greatest good for the greatest number" is impossible. Here he is saying that it is impossible to maximize both 17: 556:, argue that such an ethical framework avoids the Repugnant Conclusion and leads to few, if any, counterintuitive results. 244: 87: 736: 254: 363: 189: 779: 537: 410:'s question, "Is it total or average happiness that we seek to make a maximum?". They are theories of 72: 784: 184: 477:
Average utilitarianism may lead to repugnant conclusions if practiced strictly. Aspects of Parfit's
516: 169: 774: 356: 289: 274: 154: 34: 531:
Average utilitarianism is treated as being so obvious that it does not need any explanation in
451: 324: 314: 179: 626: 478: 443: 279: 724: 174: 106: 732: 655: 8: 692: 593: 512: 284: 159: 636: 570: 471: 334: 249: 164: 565: 411: 346: 329: 507:
The hazards of average utilitarianism are potentially avoided if it is applied more
239: 119: 666:
Sikora, R: "Is it wrong to prevent the existence of future generations?", . , 1978
552:
Proponents of the so-called "negative average preference utilitarianism", such as
483: 467: 294: 77: 751: 542: 532: 432: 427: 407: 399: 124: 114: 82: 42: 768: 422: 92: 687: 447: 134: 319: 731:, Vol. 162, No. 3859 (December 13, 1968), pp. 1243-1248. Also available 470:
utility among a group's members. So a group of 100 people each with 100
747: 675: 553: 508: 234: 129: 67: 62: 229: 214: 219: 523:) and it is only once a person drops below this threshold that we 613:. Hackett Publishing Co, Inc; 7th Revised edition. p. xxxvi. 403: 224: 209: 57: 450:
terms this "the repugnant conclusion", believing it to be
631:. United Kingdom. pp. Book 4, chapter 1, section 2. 598:. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2022. 466:
Average utilitarianism values the maximization of the
402:
that seek to maximize the average or total amount of
442:The main problem for total utilitarianism is the " 588: 586: 766: 583: 511:. For instance, the practical application of 364: 752:Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism" 495:It is also exemplified when Nozick writes: 641:: CS1 maint: location missing publisher ( 371: 357: 649: 461: 623: 608: 421: 417: 14: 767: 708: 727:(section "What shall we maximize?"), 717: 669: 704: 702: 24: 25: 796: 699: 609:Sidgwick, Henry (January 1981). 741: 681: 660: 617: 602: 255:Utilitarian social choice rule 13: 1: 756:Journal of Philosophy of Life 576: 725:"The Tragedy of the Commons" 7: 559: 541:, where he points out that 426:"the point up to which, on 10: 801: 711:Anarchy, State, and Utopia 538:The Tragedy of the Commons 27:Variants of utilitarianism 656:The repugnant conclusion 624:Sidgwick, Henry (1907). 517:two-level utilitarianism 709:Nozick, Robert (1974). 595:The Nonidentity Problem 290:Replaceability argument 275:Demandingness objection 148:Types of utilitarianism 73:Claude Adrien HelvĂ©tius 676:Average Utilitarianism 501: 493: 462:Average utilitarianism 435: 325:Neoclassical economics 315:Rational choice theory 18:Average utilitarianism 678:requires subscription 627:The Methods of Ethics 497: 488: 479:mere addition paradox 444:mere addition paradox 425: 280:Mere addition paradox 418:Total utilitarianism 388:total utilitarianism 758:, 2012; 2(1): 55-66 693:Reasons and Persons 513:rule utilitarianism 285:Paradox of hedonism 245:Equal consideration 571:Ecological fallacy 436: 398:) are variants of 335:Effective altruism 250:Felicific calculus 780:Population ethics 611:Methods of Ethics 566:Population ethics 521:intense suffering 412:population ethics 381: 380: 347:Philosophy portal 330:Population ethics 88:Francis Hutcheson 16:(Redirected from 792: 785:Ethical theories 759: 745: 739: 723:Garrett Hardin, 721: 715: 714: 706: 697: 685: 679: 673: 667: 664: 658: 653: 647: 646: 640: 632: 621: 615: 614: 606: 600: 599: 590: 373: 366: 359: 240:Consequentialism 120:John Stuart Mill 30: 29: 21: 800: 799: 795: 794: 793: 791: 790: 789: 765: 764: 763: 762: 746: 742: 722: 718: 707: 700: 686: 682: 674: 670: 665: 661: 654: 650: 634: 633: 622: 618: 607: 603: 592: 591: 584: 579: 562: 484:utility monster 464: 420: 377: 341: 340: 339: 309: 301: 300: 299: 295:Utility monster 269: 261: 260: 259: 204: 196: 195: 194: 149: 141: 140: 139: 109: 99: 98: 97: 78:Cesare Beccaria 52: 28: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 798: 788: 787: 782: 777: 775:Utilitarianism 761: 760: 740: 716: 698: 680: 668: 659: 648: 616: 601: 581: 580: 578: 575: 574: 573: 568: 561: 558: 543:Jeremy Bentham 533:Garrett Hardin 463: 460: 433:Henry Sidgwick 419: 416: 408:Henry Sidgwick 400:utilitarianism 379: 378: 376: 375: 368: 361: 353: 350: 349: 343: 342: 338: 337: 332: 327: 322: 317: 311: 310: 308:Related topics 307: 306: 303: 302: 298: 297: 292: 287: 282: 277: 271: 270: 267: 266: 263: 262: 258: 257: 252: 247: 242: 237: 232: 227: 222: 217: 212: 206: 205: 202: 201: 198: 197: 193: 192: 187: 182: 177: 172: 167: 162: 157: 151: 150: 147: 146: 143: 142: 138: 137: 132: 127: 125:Henry Sidgwick 122: 117: 115:Jeremy Bentham 111: 110: 107:Key proponents 105: 104: 101: 100: 96: 95: 90: 85: 83:William Godwin 80: 75: 70: 65: 60: 54: 53: 50: 49: 46: 45: 43:Utilitarianism 39: 38: 26: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 797: 786: 783: 781: 778: 776: 773: 772: 770: 757: 753: 749: 744: 738: 734: 730: 726: 720: 713:. p. 41. 712: 705: 703: 695: 694: 689: 684: 677: 672: 663: 657: 652: 644: 638: 630: 628: 620: 612: 605: 597: 596: 589: 587: 582: 572: 569: 567: 564: 563: 557: 555: 550: 548: 544: 540: 539: 534: 529: 526: 522: 518: 514: 510: 509:pragmatically 505: 500: 496: 492: 487: 485: 480: 475: 473: 469: 459: 455: 454:undesirable. 453: 449: 445: 440: 434: 429: 424: 415: 413: 409: 405: 401: 397: 393: 390:(also called 389: 385: 374: 369: 367: 362: 360: 355: 354: 352: 351: 348: 345: 344: 336: 333: 331: 328: 326: 323: 321: 318: 316: 313: 312: 305: 304: 296: 293: 291: 288: 286: 283: 281: 278: 276: 273: 272: 265: 264: 256: 253: 251: 248: 246: 243: 241: 238: 236: 233: 231: 228: 226: 223: 221: 218: 216: 213: 211: 208: 207: 200: 199: 191: 188: 186: 183: 181: 178: 176: 173: 171: 168: 166: 163: 161: 158: 156: 153: 152: 145: 144: 136: 133: 131: 128: 126: 123: 121: 118: 116: 113: 112: 108: 103: 102: 94: 93:William Paley 91: 89: 86: 84: 81: 79: 76: 74: 71: 69: 66: 64: 61: 59: 56: 55: 48: 47: 44: 41: 40: 36: 32: 31: 19: 755: 743: 728: 719: 710: 691: 683: 671: 662: 651: 625: 619: 610: 604: 594: 551: 546: 536: 530: 524: 520: 506: 502: 498: 494: 489: 476: 465: 456: 441: 437: 406:; following 395: 391: 387: 383: 382: 203:Key concepts 135:Peter Singer 51:Predecessors 452:intuitively 428:Utilitarian 320:Game theory 769:Categories 577:References 554:Roger Chao 547:population 235:Eudaimonia 185:Preference 130:R. M. Hare 68:David Hume 63:Shantideva 637:cite book 629:(7th ed.) 535:'s essay 515:(or else 392:averagism 230:Happiness 215:Suffering 190:Classical 170:Two-level 696:, ch. 19 560:See also 396:totalism 268:Problems 220:Pleasure 155:Negative 35:a series 33:Part of 729:Science 468:average 404:utility 384:Average 225:Utility 180:Average 688:Parfit 472:hedons 448:Parfit 737:here. 525:begin 175:Total 748:Chao 735:and 733:here 643:link 394:and 386:and 210:Pain 160:Rule 58:Mozi 750:, " 165:Act 771:: 754:, 701:^ 690:, 639:}} 635:{{ 585:^ 37:on 645:) 372:e 365:t 358:v 20:)

Index

Average utilitarianism
a series
Utilitarianism
Mozi
Shantideva
David Hume
Claude Adrien Helvétius
Cesare Beccaria
William Godwin
Francis Hutcheson
William Paley
Key proponents
Jeremy Bentham
John Stuart Mill
Henry Sidgwick
R. M. Hare
Peter Singer
Negative
Rule
Act
Two-level
Total
Average
Preference
Classical
Pain
Suffering
Pleasure
Utility
Happiness

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑