Knowledge

Julius Bahnsen

Source đź“ť

563:, until they eventually fell out and became philosophical rivals. This is not surprising, as both thinkers had similar philosophical beginnings and influences, yet differed crucially in their interpretation of these influences. Hartmann placed Schopenhauer's idea of an ever-desiring will within the unconscious psyche of the subject, while accepting Hegel's underlying rationalism and historicism. Hartmann had an affinity for pantheist monism, and asserted that the will and the rational spirit were ultimately one and the same. In contrast, Bahnsen rejected Hegel's rationalism and accepted his dialectic in a negative form, while integrating it with a pluralized version of Schopenhauer's metaphysics of will. This is a rather ironic demonstration of Bahnsen's idea of 370:(1877). Since the nature of unreasonableness consists in contradiction—particularly the contemporaneous existence of multiple will directions attaching themselves to each other—it follows that not only reality is a continuous struggle of material contrasts (real-dialectic), but that the inside of each individual is addicted to the insolvable antagonism of opposite will directions (will collisions) as well. Bahnsen negates a redemption of the countless will units ("will henades", as he expresses it himself) and postulates the permanence of the existence of the contradiction as a basic nature of the world, whereby the law of this world becomes a tragic world order. 746:, attempting to distinguish his own pessimism from that of his contemporaries. According to this article, Bahnsen found his position to be opposed to idealistic optimism and deprecating cynicism. He stated that the pessimist preserves his "idealist heart" but utilizes the "cold calculation of the head" to strike a middle ground. Thus, the pessimist realizes that alleviating the suffering of all (even of one) is next to impossible, yet the grief caused by this impossibility strengthens the pessimist's tireless pursuit of this goal, instead of demoralizing him/her. Because he feels the "weltschmerz" of being, he is fueled even further by empathy and compassion. 659:
expense of another. ... Because duties and values conflict, and because the tragic hero or heroine must act on some duty or value in a particular situation, he or she has no choice but to sin; they must violate another duty or disregard another basic value; and for that infraction or transgression they must be punished. The essence of a tragedy, then, is that we must do the right or act for the good, but that we will also be punished for it because we cannot help violating other duties and goods. Even with the best intentions and the most scrupulous conscience, we end up doing something bad and wrong, for which we must pay.
764: 641:. In his own time, the acclaimed theories of tragedy were those of Schiller and Hegel. For them, the correct moral choice in a tragic hero's circumstances is always clear and extremely painful, precisely because of these circumstances. i.e. no matter how clear this choice is, it is always difficult to choose it. A good example is Hegel, who claims that we must always choose the good of the collective, regardless of how difficult this would be for the particular individual. Bahnsen disagreed with such a notion. For him, a 1205: 1195: 33: 527:, for a will-to-nothingness is still a form of willing, and willing non-willing is a contradiction. Yet it is not impossible for the intellect to have such ideas as, according to Bahnsen, all ideas bred by the intellect are contradictory as the will's desires are irrational and eternally in conflict with themselves. This extremely pessimistic worldview, which offers no escape for the 591:
essential feature to it. Hartmann defended himself by claiming that the will itself was irrational and precisely because of this, it needed the spirit to direct it towards a goal. Otherwise, creation could not have occurred. The representations we observe are the will's only goals and these representations are evidently rational. Bahnsen countered that
468:, Bahnsen realized that the metaphysical notion of an irrational will underlying all of creation was just what he needed in his own system. After several years of studying Schopenhauer's works, Bahnsen became very proficient and knowledgeable in the "philosophy of will". He was regarded as one of the most capable philosophers in the 645:
is never obvious; there's not even a clear choice to be had. In tragedy, the hero must choose between his duties and/or his values. Whatever he chooses, he will sin and be punished for not choosing the other (punished either by law or by guilt). From this observation, Bahnsen concluded that tragedy
608:
Additionally, Bahnsen disagreed with Hartmann on fundamental points. If the will and the (rational) ideas are different (as Hartmann claimed), how do the Ideas influence the Will at all if they don't have a will of their own? Hartmann would claim that they are "different, yet unified", staying true
749:
Bahnsen was critical of "hedonistic" pessimism - the position that the pains of the world outnumber its pleasures in quality and quantity. Once more, the philosopher reasserted his convictions regarding individualism and claimed that such a calculus was impossible to make, as it would measure each
658:
The very heart of tragedy, for Bahnsen, consists in two fundamental facts: first, that the individual has to choose between conflicting duties or incommensurable values; and second, that he or she will be punished, or have to suffer, because he or she obeys one duty or honours one value at the
590:
could not be combined with the Schopenhauerian will, Bahnsen asserted, because this geist is teleological and has always had an end-goal. The will has no goals for that would require rationality and Schopenhauer was clear that the intellect was only an accidental slave to the will, and not an
679:
and regret, Bahnsen had already foreseen these conclusions. He complained that a typical Christian missionary would claim that one should just "do the right thing and be rewarded", yet there is not one "right" thing. Each moral choice has consequences and all of them have both advantages and
451:
Yet Bahnsen's philosophical system was only taking its very first steps. He accepted a "modified" form of Hegel's dialectic, but by removing the metaphysical driving entity, there remained a void to be filled in his worldview. This led to Bahnsen's accidental discovery of the
750:
individual differently. There are other reasons to be pessimistic about the world, he claimed: To realize that all moral aims and ideals are futile, yet to pursue them nonetheless, knowing full well that there is no exit or salvation — that is true pessimism.
585:
and claimed that the common point between all "individual wills" is a singular will. Whilst Bahnsen criticized Hartmann, claiming that his "Hegelian rationalism" corrupted the teachings of Schopenhauer's essentially purposeless will. Hegel's
397:, which was in decline yet still popular in early 19th century Germany. From Hegel's teachings, Bahnsen found his panlogism and radical rationalism dissatisfying. In Bahnsen's view, there was a stark mismatch between the unconcealed 511:, with their own specific cravings, aims and wishes. However, these individual wills ("will henades") suffer from contradictory desires due to their irrational nature. This is the result of Bahnsen's combination of Schopenhauer's 443:
between two opposing forces. The opposition results only in negation and the consequent destruction of contradicting aspects. For Bahnsen, no rationality was to be found in being and thus, there was no
698:
During the end of his life, Bahnsen completed his philosophical project. Despite constant editions and slight changes in details, three principle premises remained throughout Bahnsen's philosophy:
718:
and do not take into consideration the unique reality of the individual wills of other people. For this reason and for other more technical purposes, Bahnsen agreed with his fellow pessimists
351:
is still accepted as the essence of the world and the only thing real, it doesn't regard the will as being the same within all individuals, but as just as manifold as these individuals.
1130:
Das Tragische als Weltgesetz und der Humor als ästhetische Gestalt des Metaphysischen. ("The Tragical as World Law and Humour as Aesthetic Shape of the Metaphysical.")
523:, and that of Bahnsen is that, in Bahnsen's philosophical system — there is no salvation. For Bahnsen, without the will the intellect is impotent. It cannot "will" 613:. Yet, this would appear as a contradiction to Bahnsen and would further solidify the power of Bahnsen's own convictions and conclusions stemming from his 1299: 401:
of the world and the naive theories, rationalizations and explanations of various philosophers. Existence itself seemed harsh, confusing and downright
663:
This is why Bahnsen claims that ultimately, reason cannot help us in our lives and that our choices must be dictated by feeling. A few years before
597:
is the will's non-representational goal and that not all of the will's aims are rational. This debate could not be resolved, as Hartmann regarded
1274: 1284: 1294: 1249: 1239: 1329: 1264: 1158:, Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life, vol. 7, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 105–114, 1304: 1171: 1031: 731: 710:
Other than rejecting Hegel's progressivism and reinterpreting Schopenhauer's singular will, Bahnsen also denied all forms of
693: 684:
as almost sacred. It alone gives us the ability to "laugh off" the tragedy of being and to avoid the clutches of depression.
320: 139: 1309: 1244: 1199: 409:
appealing. The dialectic explained the ingrained opposition of the world with itself in a cycle of perpetual conflict (as
1319: 1289: 605:, while Bahnsen could not bring himself to accept the unprovable reality of this so-called "unconscious representation". 413:
had observed in his fragments centuries earlier). However, Bahnsen believed that Heraclitus's postulate of an underlying
491:. He viewed each person as unique and as a result of this view, could not entirely accept Schopenhauer's preference for 1324: 1314: 1254: 807: 785: 778: 476:. However, as Bahnsen's own system matured, he began to deviate from Schopenhauer's teachings in considerable ways. 519:. A crucial difference between Schopenhauer's worldview, which offers salvation for some via the freed Intellect's 453: 1259: 727: 560: 540: 496: 964: 531:, differentiates Bahnsen not only from Schopenhauer, but also from the rest of his pessimistic contemporaries ( 129: 543:). His ideas are arguably more unsettling than Mainländer's notion of a will-to-die, yet strangely similar to 336: 111: 701:
1) Contradiction exists in the heart of reality, and is not a mere attribute of our thoughts about reality
1269: 304: 296: 292: 772: 512: 124: 354:
This characterological element of Bahnsen's teachings, on which the works of such philosophers as
743: 711: 94: 520: 789: 582: 504: 288: 268: 134: 119: 233: 723: 719: 536: 532: 500: 473: 1279: 1234: 1229: 646:
exposes precisely this inner contradiction that is inherent in the world. In his 2016 work
528: 311:. Various employments as a teacher followed. In 1862, Bahnsen acquired an employment at a 8: 924: 892: 860: 844: 828: 651: 544: 465: 457: 332: 393:
At the beginning of his delve into philosophy, Julius Bahnsen developed an interest in
312: 300: 280: 276: 104: 1215:
Das Tragische als Weltgesetz und der Humor als ästhetische Gestalt des Metaphysischen
1167: 1037: 1027: 973: 348: 1209: 1159: 1137:
Wie ich wurde, was ich ward, nebst anderen StĂĽcken aus dem NachlaĂź des Philosophen.
429:. As a response to this "misunderstanding", Bahnsen developed his own idea of the 1214: 1021: 908: 876: 617:. As for Hartmann, he did not accept Bahnsen's theories and diagnosed him with a 602: 340: 1163: 548: 484: 421:
had misled them and had contaminated Hegel's formulation of the dialectic with
381:(1880/82), and his anniversary publication to the jubilee of the city TĂĽbingen 225: 1151: 960:. Journal of Nietzsche Studies Vol. 47, No. 1 (Spring 2016). pp. 101–118. 621:
and a philosophical inability to distinguish "conflict" from "contradiction".
1223: 1041: 668: 422: 398: 355: 195: 79: 1156:
All Too Human: Laughter, Humor, and Comedy in Nineteenth-Century Philosophy
571: 488: 383:
The Tragical as World Law and Humour as Aesthetic Shape of the Metaphysical
161: 373:
The real-dialectical side of his teachings Bahnsen laid down in the paper
347:. Though in this connection the reasonless, all-embracing Schopenhauerian 339:
dialectic (which Bahnsen, however, accepted only within the realms of the
672: 524: 461: 426: 394: 241: 221: 166: 240:(1867) and developed forth with his following works, amongst others his 499:
of a singular metaphysical entity). Similar to fellow German pessimist
480: 410: 308: 264: 171: 156: 405:. Starting out from these premises, Bahnsen found Hegel's idea of the 303:
army in 1850. There he studied philosophy and in 1853 graduated under
1152:"Humor as Redemption in the Pessimistic Philosophy of Julius Bahnsen" 715: 676: 664: 587: 445: 418: 406: 272: 260: 229: 57: 316: 256: 75: 53: 915:, The Philosophical Review Vol. 41, No. 4 (Jul., 1932), pp. 368-384 883:, The Philosophical Review Vol. 41, No. 4 (Jul., 1932), pp. 368-384 680:
disadvantages. In the face of such a dire existence, Bahnsen views
1194: 630: 593: 284: 176: 32: 945:. University of Illinois Press, 2008. pp. 39, 48, 55, 140. 681: 610: 492: 472:, rivalled only by Schopenhauer's personal literary executor — 344: 1026:(1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 264. 568: 559:
Bahnsen developed a close friendship with fellow philosopher
414: 1072:
Nietzsche's Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography
943:
Nietzsche's Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography
448:
power that led to progress at the end of every conflict.
379:
The Contradiction in the Knowledge and Being of the World
245:
The Contradiction in the Knowledge and Being of the World
913:
Julius Bahnsen, Philosopher of Heroic Despair, 1830-1881
881:
Julius Bahnsen, Philosopher of Heroic Despair, 1830-1881
737: 495:(the idea that every person and every thing is merely a 483:, specifically the method of examination of individual 1117:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
1102:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
1087:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
1023:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
1007:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
992:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
958:
Julius Bahnsen's Influence on Nietzsche's Wills-Theory
929:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
897:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
865:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
849:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
833:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
648:
Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860-1900
1150:
Beiser, Frederick C. (2018), Moland, Lydia L. (ed.),
507:
and asserted that there is no unified will, but only
970: 742:
At the end of his life, Bahnsen wrote an article on
704:
2) Contradiction does not get resolved in synthesis
1128:Julius Bahnsen, Winfried H. MĂĽller-Seyfarth (Ed.): 1119:. Oxford University Press, 2016. pp. 281–285. 1104:. Oxford University Press, 2016. pp. 263–267. 1074:. University of Illinois Press, 2008. p. 140. 1009:. Oxford University Press, 2016. pp. 246–263. 994:. Oxford University Press, 2016. pp. 229–244. 972: 224:. Bahnsen is usually considered the originator of 654:expresses Bahnsen's theory of tragedy as follows: 1221: 931:, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 233. 899:, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 263. 867:, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 229. 851:, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 230. 835:, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 246. 714:. For him, the ideas of idealism are inherently 554: 220:(30 March 1830 – 7 December 1881) was a German 1089:. Oxford University Press, 2016. p. 267. 578:created contention within their friendship. 193: 707:3) The source of contradiction is the will 479:Bahnsen had always harbored an interest in 364:On the Relationship Between Will and Motive 1132:VanBremen VerlagsBuchhandlung, Berlin 1995 1059:. pp. Section: An Ecstatic Discourse. 31: 1300:19th-century German educational theorists 808:Learn how and when to remove this message 687: 971:Compare with Leibniz, Gottfried (1965). 771:This article includes a list of general 734:is superior to transcendental idealism. 633:derived directly and naturally from the 567:, as Bahnsen and Hartmann's interest in 1054: 1222: 1149: 1019: 464:and discussing it personally with the 989: 738:Bahnsen's interpretation of pessimism 694:Transcendental realism (Schopenhauer) 650:the American professor of philosophy 326: 263:, in 1830 Bahnsen began his study of 236:which he laid down in his two-volume 1135:Julius Bahnsen, Anselm Ruest (Ed.): 757: 624: 515:metaphysic and his own ideas of the 362:(1867) as well as the disquisitions 358:are built upon, is laid down in the 1069: 940: 13: 1275:People from the Duchy of Schleswig 1143: 1114: 1099: 1084: 1004: 955: 777:it lacks sufficient corresponding 323:, where he lived until his death. 14: 1341: 1187: 979:. Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill Co. 460:. After carefully examining this 417:and Hegel's idea of the rational 1295:German philosophers of education 1250:19th-century German philosophers 1240:19th-century German male writers 1206:Works by or about Julius Bahnsen 1193: 762: 454:World as Will and Representation 1285:People from Tønder Municipality 1265:German male non-fiction writers 1108: 1093: 1078: 1063: 1048: 1013: 998: 983: 728:Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann 561:Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann 360:Contributions to Characterology 238:Contributions to Characterology 218:Julius Friedrich August Bahnsen 1305:German philosophers of history 949: 934: 918: 902: 886: 870: 854: 838: 822: 581:Hartmann criticized Bahnsen's 203:Tragic conception of the world 130:Post-Schopenhauerian pessimism 16:German philosopher (1830–1881) 1: 1330:University of TĂĽbingen alumni 1020:Beiser, Frederick C. (2016). 753: 388: 307:with a topic relating to the 555:Correspondence with Hartmann 375:On the Philosophy of History 335:, Bahnsen dared a merger of 250: 7: 1310:German philosophers of mind 1245:19th-century German writers 1164:10.1007/978-3-319-91331-5_7 279:. From 1849 he fought as a 10: 1346: 1320:Philosophers of psychology 1290:German philosophers of art 691: 603:unconscious representation 565:existence as contradiction 1325:University of Kiel alumni 1315:Philosophers of pessimism 503:, Bahnsen leaned towards 439:, there was no notion of 377:(1871), his central work 305:Friedrich Theodor Vischer 211: 184: 148: 110: 100: 90: 86: 64: 39: 30: 23: 1255:Continental philosophers 574:both drew them together 291:(1848–1851) and fled to 234:philosophical reflection 125:Metaphysical voluntarism 792:more precise citations. 619:psychopathic melancholy 368:Mosaics and Silhouettes 299:after the disarming of 95:19th-century philosophy 1260:German epistemologists 1198:Quotations related to 732:transcendental realism 688:Transcendental realism 677:choices lead to sorrow 661: 297:Kingdom of WĂĽrttemberg 289:First War of Schleswig 269:Gregor Wilhelm Nitzsch 194: 140:Transcendental realism 120:Continental philosophy 656: 521:silencing of the will 505:ontological pluralism 466:Frankfurt philosopher 343:) and Schopenhauer's 1055:Kierkegaard, Soren. 925:Beiser, Frederick C. 893:Beiser, Frederick C. 861:Beiser, Frederick C. 845:Beiser, Frederick C. 829:Beiser, Frederick C. 629:Bahnsen's theory of 301:Schleswig-Holstein's 1115:Beiser, Frederick. 1100:Beiser, Frederick. 1085:Beiser, Frederick. 1005:Beiser, Frederick. 990:Frederick, Beiser. 652:Frederick C. Beiser 545:Friedrich Nietszche 470:Schopenhauer Schule 458:Arthur Schopenhauer 724:Philipp Mainländer 720:Julius Frauenstädt 501:Philipp Mainländer 474:Julius Frauenstädt 327:Philosophical work 317:Lauenburg (LÄ™bork) 105:Western philosophy 1173:978-3-319-91331-5 1070:Brobjer, Thomas. 1033:978-0-19-876871-5 956:Jensen, Anthony. 941:Brobjer, Thomas. 818: 817: 810: 625:Theory of tragedy 331:As a disciple of 215: 214: 1337: 1270:Metaphilosophers 1210:Internet Archive 1197: 1183: 1182: 1180: 1121: 1120: 1112: 1106: 1105: 1097: 1091: 1090: 1082: 1076: 1075: 1067: 1061: 1060: 1052: 1046: 1045: 1017: 1011: 1010: 1002: 996: 995: 987: 981: 980: 978: 968: 962: 961: 953: 947: 946: 938: 932: 922: 916: 906: 900: 890: 884: 874: 868: 858: 852: 842: 836: 826: 813: 806: 802: 799: 793: 788:this article by 779:inline citations 766: 765: 758: 509:individual wills 199: 71: 49: 47: 35: 21: 20: 1345: 1344: 1340: 1339: 1338: 1336: 1335: 1334: 1220: 1219: 1190: 1178: 1176: 1174: 1146: 1144:Further reading 1125: 1124: 1113: 1109: 1098: 1094: 1083: 1079: 1068: 1064: 1053: 1049: 1034: 1018: 1014: 1003: 999: 988: 984: 969: 965: 954: 950: 939: 935: 923: 919: 909:Harry Slochower 907: 903: 891: 887: 877:Harry Slochower 875: 871: 859: 855: 843: 839: 827: 823: 814: 803: 797: 794: 784:Please help to 783: 767: 763: 756: 740: 696: 690: 675:wrote that all 627: 557: 547:'s idea of the 391: 329: 253: 207: 204: 187: 151: 144: 82: 73: 69: 68:7 December 1881 60: 51: 45: 43: 26: 17: 12: 11: 5: 1343: 1333: 1332: 1327: 1322: 1317: 1312: 1307: 1302: 1297: 1292: 1287: 1282: 1277: 1272: 1267: 1262: 1257: 1252: 1247: 1242: 1237: 1232: 1218: 1217: 1212: 1203: 1200:Julius Bahnsen 1189: 1188:External links 1186: 1185: 1184: 1172: 1145: 1142: 1141: 1140: 1133: 1123: 1122: 1107: 1092: 1077: 1062: 1047: 1032: 1012: 997: 982: 963: 948: 933: 917: 901: 885: 869: 853: 837: 820: 819: 816: 815: 798:September 2022 770: 768: 761: 755: 752: 739: 736: 692:Main article: 689: 686: 667:developed his 626: 623: 556: 553: 549:eternal return 390: 387: 328: 325: 252: 249: 226:characterology 213: 212: 209: 208: 206: 205: 202: 200: 190: 188: 185: 182: 181: 180: 179: 174: 169: 164: 159: 152: 150:Main interests 149: 146: 145: 143: 142: 137: 132: 127: 122: 116: 114: 108: 107: 102: 98: 97: 92: 88: 87: 84: 83: 74: 72:(aged 51) 66: 62: 61: 52: 41: 37: 36: 28: 27: 25:Julius Bahnsen 24: 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 1342: 1331: 1328: 1326: 1323: 1321: 1318: 1316: 1313: 1311: 1308: 1306: 1303: 1301: 1298: 1296: 1293: 1291: 1288: 1286: 1283: 1281: 1278: 1276: 1273: 1271: 1268: 1266: 1263: 1261: 1258: 1256: 1253: 1251: 1248: 1246: 1243: 1241: 1238: 1236: 1233: 1231: 1228: 1227: 1225: 1216: 1213: 1211: 1207: 1204: 1201: 1196: 1192: 1191: 1175: 1169: 1165: 1161: 1157: 1153: 1148: 1147: 1138: 1134: 1131: 1127: 1126: 1118: 1111: 1103: 1096: 1088: 1081: 1073: 1066: 1058: 1051: 1043: 1039: 1035: 1029: 1025: 1024: 1016: 1008: 1001: 993: 986: 977: 976: 967: 959: 952: 944: 937: 930: 926: 921: 914: 910: 905: 898: 894: 889: 882: 878: 873: 866: 862: 857: 850: 846: 841: 834: 830: 825: 821: 812: 809: 801: 791: 787: 781: 780: 774: 769: 760: 759: 751: 747: 745: 735: 733: 729: 725: 721: 717: 713: 708: 705: 702: 699: 695: 685: 683: 678: 674: 670: 669:perspectivism 666: 660: 655: 653: 649: 644: 640: 639:Realdialektik 637:ideas of his 636: 635:contradictory 632: 622: 620: 616: 615:Realdialektik 612: 606: 604: 600: 596: 595: 589: 584: 579: 577: 573: 570: 566: 562: 552: 550: 546: 542: 538: 534: 530: 526: 522: 518: 517:Realdialektik 514: 513:voluntaristic 510: 506: 502: 498: 494: 490: 486: 482: 477: 475: 471: 467: 463: 459: 455: 449: 447: 442: 438: 437:Realdialektik 434: 433: 432:Realdialektik 428: 424: 423:progressivism 420: 416: 412: 408: 404: 403:contradictory 400: 399:irrationality 396: 386: 384: 380: 376: 371: 369: 365: 361: 357: 356:Ludwig Klages 352: 350: 346: 342: 338: 334: 324: 322: 321:Hinterpommern 318: 314: 310: 306: 302: 298: 294: 290: 286: 282: 278: 274: 270: 266: 262: 258: 248: 246: 243: 239: 235: 231: 227: 223: 219: 210: 201: 198: 197: 196:Realdialektik 192: 191: 189: 186:Notable ideas 183: 178: 175: 173: 170: 168: 165: 163: 160: 158: 155: 154: 153: 147: 141: 138: 136: 133: 131: 128: 126: 123: 121: 118: 117: 115: 113: 109: 106: 103: 99: 96: 93: 89: 85: 81: 80:Hinterpommern 77: 67: 63: 59: 55: 50:30 March 1830 42: 38: 34: 29: 22: 19: 1202:at Wikiquote 1177:, retrieved 1155: 1139:Leipzig 1931 1136: 1129: 1116: 1110: 1101: 1095: 1086: 1080: 1071: 1065: 1057:Either/Order 1056: 1050: 1022: 1015: 1006: 1000: 991: 985: 974: 966: 957: 951: 942: 936: 928: 920: 912: 904: 896: 888: 880: 872: 864: 856: 848: 840: 832: 824: 804: 795: 776: 748: 741: 709: 706: 703: 700: 697: 662: 657: 647: 643:clear choice 642: 638: 634: 628: 618: 614: 607: 598: 592: 580: 575: 572:philosophers 564: 558: 516: 508: 489:temperaments 478: 469: 450: 446:teleological 440: 436: 431: 430: 402: 392: 382: 378: 374: 372: 367: 363: 359: 353: 333:Schopenhauer 330: 313:progymnasium 283:against the 254: 244: 237: 217: 216: 162:epistemology 70:(1881-12-07) 18: 1280:Ontologists 1235:1881 deaths 1230:1830 births 790:introducing 716:solipsistic 673:Kierkegaard 533:Frauenstädt 525:nothingness 462:magnum opus 427:historicism 395:Hegelianism 366:(1870) and 267:and (under 247:(1880/82). 242:magnum opus 230:dialectical 228:and a real- 222:philosopher 167:metaphysics 1224:Categories 1179:2 November 975:Monadology 773:references 754:References 537:Mainländer 485:characters 481:psychology 411:Heraclitus 389:Philosophy 309:aesthetics 265:philosophy 232:method of 172:psychology 157:Aesthetics 46:1830-03-30 1042:929590292 744:pessimism 665:Nietzsche 583:pluralism 441:synthesis 435:. In the 407:dialectic 281:volunteer 273:philology 261:Schleswig 251:Biography 135:Pluralism 58:Schleswig 712:idealism 541:Hartmann 385:(1877). 341:abstract 293:TĂĽbingen 255:Born in 1208:at the 786:improve 631:tragedy 609:to his 599:feeling 594:feeling 529:subject 337:Hegel's 295:in the 287:in the 177:tragedy 1170:  1040:  1030:  775:, but 682:humour 611:monism 601:as an 588:spirit 493:monism 419:spirit 345:monism 257:Tønder 112:School 101:Region 76:LÄ™bork 54:Tønder 730:that 497:modus 415:Logos 285:Danes 1181:2021 1168:ISBN 1038:OCLC 1028:ISBN 726:and 671:and 569:both 487:and 425:and 349:will 277:Kiel 65:Died 40:Born 1160:doi 576:and 456:by 315:in 275:in 91:Era 1226:: 1166:, 1154:, 1036:. 927:, 911:, 895:, 879:, 863:, 847:, 831:, 722:, 551:. 539:, 535:, 319:, 271:) 259:, 78:, 56:, 1162:: 1044:. 811:) 805:( 800:) 796:( 782:. 48:) 44:(

Index


Tønder
Schleswig
Lębork
Hinterpommern
19th-century philosophy
Western philosophy
School
Continental philosophy
Metaphysical voluntarism
Post-Schopenhauerian pessimism
Pluralism
Transcendental realism
Aesthetics
epistemology
metaphysics
psychology
tragedy
Realdialektik
philosopher
characterology
dialectical
philosophical reflection
magnum opus
Tønder
Schleswig
philosophy
Gregor Wilhelm Nitzsch
philology
Kiel

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑