Knowledge

Cartesian circle

Source đź“ť

20: 71:– that whatever one clearly and distinctly perceives is true: "I now seem to be able to lay it down as a general rule that whatever I perceive very clearly and distinctly is true" (AT VII 35). He goes on in the same Meditation to argue for the existence of a benevolent God, in order to defeat his skeptical argument in the first Meditation that God might be a deceiver. He then says that without his knowledge of God's existence, none of his knowledge could be certain. 199:. Frankfurt suggests that Descartes's arguments for the existence of God, and for the reliability of reason, are not intended to prove that their conclusions are true, but to show that reason leads to them. Thus, reason is validated by being shown to confirm its own validity instead of leading to a denial of its validity by being shown to be incapable of demonstrating the existence of a benevolent God. 124:
Descartes' own response to this criticism, in his "Author's Replies to the Fourth Set of Objections", is first to give what has become known as the Memory response; he points out that in the fifth Meditation (at AT VII 69–70) he did not say that he needed God to guarantee the truth of his clear and
159:
presents the memory defense as follows: "When one is actually intuiting a given proposition, no doubt can be entertained. So any doubt there can be must be entertained when one is not intuiting the proposition." He goes on to argue: "The trouble with Descartes's system is not that it is circular;
113:
You are not yet certain of the existence of God, and you say that you are not certain of anything. It follows from this that you do not yet clearly and distinctly know that you are a thinking thing, since, on your own admission, that knowledge depends on the clear knowledge of an existing God; and
129:
When I said that we can know nothing for certain until we are aware that God exists, I expressly declared that I was speaking only of knowledge of those conclusions which can be recalled when we are no longer attending to the arguments by means of which we deduced them. (AT VII
160:
nor that there is an illegitimate relation between the proofs of God and the clear and distinct perceptions The trouble is that the proofs of God are invalid and do not convince even when they are supposedly being intuited."
144:, but recognizes it as something self-evident by a simple intuition of the mind" (AT VII 140). Finally, he points out that the certainty of clear and distinct ideas does not depend upon God's guarantee (AT VII 145–146). The 121:
was another one of Descartes' objectors, likewise arguing that God's existence cannot be used to prove that what one clearly and distinctly perceives is true.
164: 140:
is an inference: "When someone says 'I am thinking, therefore I am, or I exist' he does not deduce existence from thought by means of a
402: 385:
Carriero, John (2008). "The Cartesian Circle and the Foundations of Knowledge". In Broughton, Janet; Carriero, John (eds.).
78:
Descartes' proof of the reliability of clear and distinct perceptions takes as a premise God's existence as a non-deceiver.
114:
this you have not proved in the passage where you draw the conclusion that you clearly know what you are. (AT VII 124–125)
489: 375: 508: 370:. Vol. 2. Translated by John Cottingham; Robert Stoothoff; Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge University Press. 1984. 67: 287: 465: 513: 413: 187:
true and certain, that is, time-bound, and objectively possible (and does not need the guarantee of God).
85:
Many commentators, both at the time that Descartes wrote and since, have argued that this involves a
81:
Descartes' proofs of God's existence presuppose the reliability of clear and distinct perceptions.
19: 213: 8: 433: 208: 42: 518: 485: 437: 398: 371: 86: 46: 477: 425: 390: 156: 90: 192: 136: 118: 33: 394: 191:
Another defense of Descartes against the charge of circularity is developed by
102: 89:, as he relies upon the principle of clarity and distinctness to argue for the 39: 502: 447:
Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: the Defense of Reason in Descartes' Meditations
148:
in particular is self-verifying, indubitable, immune to the strongest doubt.
93:, and then claims that God is the guarantor of his clear and distinct ideas. 455:
Hatfield, Gary (2006). "The Cartesian Circle". In Gaukroger, Stephen (ed.).
252: 429: 74:
The Cartesian circle is a criticism of the above that takes this form:
54: 295: 141: 183:
true and certain (with the guarantee of God), while the former is
179:; both are true and cannot be contradicted, but the latter is 50: 414:"Descartes' Dualism: Correcting Some Misconceptions" 65:
Descartes argues – for example, in the third of his
171:The distinction appropriate here is that between 500: 16:Error in reasoning attributed to RenĂ© Descartes 451:Reprinted by Princeton University Press, 2007. 389:. Blackwell Publishing Ltd. pp. 302–318. 125:distinct ideas, only to guarantee his memory: 457:The Blackwell Guide to Descartes' Meditations 101:The first person to raise this criticism was 411: 339: 96: 105:, in the "Second Set of Objections" to the 232: 444: 351: 134:Secondly, he explicitly denies that the 476: 454: 384: 327: 315: 275: 18: 470:The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 368:The Philosophical Writings of Descartes 501: 482:Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry 463: 264: 237:. Oxford University Press. p. 49. 151: 57:, which is itself guaranteed by God. 418:Journal of the History of Philosophy 412:Christofidou, Andrea (April 2001). 13: 49:. He argued that the existence of 14: 530: 269: 45:attributed to French philosopher 68:Meditations on First Philosophy 60: 345: 333: 321: 309: 280: 258: 241: 226: 1: 360: 468:. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). 197:Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen 7: 464:Newman, Lex (Spring 2019). 202: 10: 535: 395:10.1002/9780470696439.ch18 251:, ed. by Charles Adam and 466:"Descartes' Epistemology" 445:Frankfurt, Harry (1970). 233:Cottingham, John (1988). 97:Descartes' contemporaries 387:A Companion to Descartes 219: 509:Philosophical arguments 288:"The Cartesian Circle" 189: 132: 116: 53:is proven by reliable 24: 430:10.1353/hph.2003.0098 169: 127: 111: 22: 249:Oeuvres de Descartes 214:Ontological argument 459:. pp. 122–141. 165:Andrea Christofidou 152:Modern commentators 38:) is an example of 514:Informal fallacies 342:, pp. 219–220 209:Circular reasoning 43:circular reasoning 25: 484:. Penguin Books. 478:Williams, Bernard 404:978-0-470-69643-9 340:Christofidou 2001 87:circular argument 526: 495: 473: 460: 450: 449:. Bobbs–Merrill. 441: 408: 381: 354: 349: 343: 337: 331: 325: 319: 313: 307: 306: 304: 303: 294:. Archived from 284: 278: 273: 267: 262: 256: 245: 239: 238: 235:The Rationalists 230: 157:Bernard Williams 91:existence of God 29:Cartesian circle 534: 533: 529: 528: 527: 525: 524: 523: 499: 498: 492: 405: 378: 366: 363: 358: 357: 350: 346: 338: 334: 326: 322: 314: 310: 301: 299: 286: 285: 281: 274: 270: 263: 259: 247:"AT" refers to 246: 242: 231: 227: 222: 205: 193:Harry Frankfurt 154: 119:Antoine Arnauld 99: 63: 31:(also known as 17: 12: 11: 5: 532: 522: 521: 516: 511: 497: 496: 490: 474: 461: 452: 442: 424:(2): 215–238. 409: 403: 382: 376: 362: 359: 356: 355: 352:Frankfurt 1970 344: 332: 320: 308: 292:www.owl232.net 279: 268: 257: 240: 224: 223: 221: 218: 217: 216: 211: 204: 201: 153: 150: 103:Marin Mersenne 98: 95: 83: 82: 79: 62: 59: 47:RenĂ© Descartes 23:RenĂ© Descartes 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 531: 520: 517: 515: 512: 510: 507: 506: 504: 493: 491:0-14-022006-2 487: 483: 479: 475: 471: 467: 462: 458: 453: 448: 443: 439: 435: 431: 427: 423: 419: 415: 410: 406: 400: 396: 392: 388: 383: 379: 377:0-521-28808-8 373: 369: 365: 364: 353: 348: 341: 336: 330:, p. 210 329: 328:Williams 1978 324: 318:, p. 206 317: 316:Williams 1978 312: 298:on 2017-10-08 297: 293: 289: 283: 277: 276:Carriero 2008 272: 266: 261: 254: 250: 244: 236: 229: 225: 215: 212: 210: 207: 206: 200: 198: 194: 188: 186: 182: 178: 174: 168: 166: 161: 158: 149: 147: 143: 139: 138: 131: 126: 122: 120: 115: 110: 108: 104: 94: 92: 88: 80: 77: 76: 75: 72: 70: 69: 58: 56: 52: 48: 44: 41: 37: 35: 30: 21: 481: 469: 456: 446: 421: 417: 386: 367: 347: 335: 323: 311: 300:. Retrieved 296:the original 291: 282: 271: 260: 253:Paul Tannery 248: 243: 234: 228: 196: 195:in his book 190: 185:subjectively 184: 180: 176: 172: 170: 162: 155: 145: 135: 133: 128: 123: 117: 112: 106: 100: 84: 73: 66: 64: 61:The argument 32: 28: 26: 265:Newman 2019 181:objectively 107:Meditations 503:Categories 361:References 302:2017-10-09 167:explains: 55:perception 40:fallacious 438:143664433 142:syllogism 36:'s circle 519:Ontology 480:(1978). 203:See also 177:scientia 173:cognitio 34:Arnauld 488:  436:  401:  374:  146:cogito 137:cogito 434:S2CID 220:Notes 486:ISBN 399:ISBN 372:ISBN 175:and 130:140) 27:The 426:doi 391:doi 163:As 51:God 505:: 432:. 422:39 420:. 416:. 397:. 290:. 109:: 494:. 472:. 440:. 428:: 407:. 393:: 380:. 305:. 255:.

Index


Arnauld
fallacious
circular reasoning
René Descartes
God
perception
Meditations on First Philosophy
circular argument
existence of God
Marin Mersenne
Antoine Arnauld
cogito
syllogism
Bernard Williams
Andrea Christofidou
Harry Frankfurt
Circular reasoning
Ontological argument
Paul Tannery
Newman 2019
Carriero 2008
"The Cartesian Circle"
the original
Williams 1978
Williams 1978
Christofidou 2001
Frankfurt 1970
ISBN
0-521-28808-8

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑