Knowledge

Primitive notion

Source 📝

96:
their meanings. At the same time we adopt the principle: not to employ any of the other expressions of the discipline under consideration, unless its meaning has first been determined with the help of primitive terms and of such expressions of the discipline whose meanings have been explained previously. The sentence which determines the meaning of a term in this way is called a DEFINITION,...
112:
To a non-mathematician it often comes as a surprise that it is impossible to define explicitly all the terms which are used. This is not a superficial problem but lies at the root of all knowledge; it is necessary to begin somewhere, and to make progress one must clearly state those elements and
95:
When we set out to construct a given discipline, we distinguish, first of all, a certain small group of expressions of this discipline that seem to us to be immediately understandable; the expressions in this group we call PRIMITIVE TERMS or UNDEFINED TERMS, and we employ them without explaining
296:
of relations are primitive. (p 25) As for denotation of objects by description, Russell acknowledges that a primitive notion is involved. (p 27) The thesis of Russell’s book is "Pure mathematics uses only a few notions, and these are logical constants." (p xxi)
202:
in Paris in 1900. The notions themselves may not necessarily need to be stated; Susan Haack (1978) writes, "A set of axioms is sometimes said to give an implicit definition of its primitive terms."
51:. Some authors refer to the latter as "defining" primitive notions by one or more axioms, but this can be misleading. Formal theories cannot dispense with primitive notions, under pain of 137:
writes: 'definition' of 'set' is less a definition than an attempt at explication of something which is being given the status of a primitive, undefined, term. As evidence, she quotes
169:
are primitive notions. Since Peano arithmetic is useful in regards to properties of the numbers, the objects that the primitive notions represent may not strictly matter.
39:
is a concept that is not defined in terms of previously-defined concepts. It is often motivated informally, usually by an appeal to
199: 141:: "A set is formed by the grouping together of single objects into a whole. A set is a plurality thought of as a unit." 601: 227: 637: 341: 253: 622: 511: 632: 593: 316: 248: 209: 77: 549: 122:
The necessity for primitive notions is illustrated in several axiomatic foundations in mathematics:
575: 491: 311: 544: 503: 419: 285: 273: 265: 105: 76:
are some primitive notions. Instead of attempting to define them, their interplay is ruled (in
40: 396: 378: 306: 277: 541:
Mechanising Hilbert's Foundations of Geometry in Isabelle (see ref 16, re: Hilbert's take)
360:
More generally, in a formal system, rules restrict the use of primitive notions. See e.g.
8: 627: 567: 445: 336: 101: 331: 223: 205: 162: 597: 281: 130: 80:) by axioms like "For every two points there exists a line that contains them both". 563: 326: 293: 257: 195: 194:: The primitive notions will depend upon the set of axioms chosen for the system. 191: 177: 158: 144: 64: 52: 44: 392: 321: 138: 56: 474:
denotes the set of points, of lines, and the "contains" relation, respectively.
412: 269: 185: 113:
relations which are undefined and those properties which are taken for granted.
616: 483: 88: 32: 280:. (pp 18,9) Regarding relations, Russell takes as primitive notions the 173: 20: 522: 261: 134: 126: 28: 361: 151:
is a primitive notion. To assert that it exists would be an implicit
148: 488:
Introduction to Logic and the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences
181: 16:
Concept that is not defined in terms of previously defined concepts
373: 272:
as a primitive notion. To establish sets, he also establishes
152: 48: 24: 276:
as primitive, as well as the phrase "such that" as used in
166: 566:(1900) "Logical introduction to any deductive theory" in 47:, relations between primitive notions are restricted by 176:: Typically, primitive notions are: real number, two 91:
explained the role of primitive notions as follows:
100:An inevitable regress to primitive notions in the 292:. Furthermore, logical products of relations and 614: 260:used the following notions: for class-calculus ( 572:A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931 543:(Master's thesis). University of Edinburgh. 538: 214:point, line, plane, congruence, betweeness 548: 376:(300 B.C.) still gave definitions in his 133:is an example of a primitive notion. As 242: 62:For example, in contemporary geometry, 615: 382:, like "A line is breadthless length". 587: 200:International Congress of Philosophy 13: 14: 649: 188:, numbers 0 and 1, ordering <. 391:This axiom can be formalized in 364:for a non-logical formal system. 198:discussed this selection at the 43:and everyday experience. In an 581: 557: 532: 516: 497: 477: 385: 367: 354: 1: 347: 342:Natural semantic metalanguage 254:The Principles of Mathematics 527:The Philosophy of Set Theory 7: 512:University of Toronto Press 300: 117: 10: 654: 594:Cambridge University Press 317:Foundations of mathematics 230:the primitive notions are 212:the primitive notions are 83: 249:philosophy of mathematics 576:Harvard University Press 508:Foundations of Geometry 492:Oxford University Press 312:Foundations of geometry 274:propositional functions 504:Gilbert de B. Robinson 286:complementary relation 210:Hilbert's axiom system 106:Gilbert de B. Robinson 78:Hilbert's axiom system 638:Mathematical concepts 588:Haack, Susan (1978), 129:: The concept of the 590:Philosophy of Logics 307:Axiomatic set theory 278:set builder notation 243:Russell's primitives 228:Peano's axiom system 623:Philosophy of logic 568:Jean van Heijenoort 539:Phil Scott (2008). 337:Notion (philosophy) 102:theory of knowledge 332:Mathematical logic 224:Euclidean geometry 206:Euclidean geometry 163:successor function 633:Concepts in logic 510:, 4th ed., p. 8, 294:relative products 282:converse relation 192:Axiomatic systems 178:binary operations 104:was explained by 645: 607: 606: 585: 579: 564:Alessandro Padoa 561: 555: 554: 552: 536: 530: 520: 514: 501: 495: 481: 475: 389: 383: 371: 365: 358: 327:Logical constant 258:Bertrand Russell 196:Alessandro Padoa 159:Peano arithmetic 145:Naive set theory 53:infinite regress 45:axiomatic theory 37:primitive notion 653: 652: 648: 647: 646: 644: 643: 642: 613: 612: 611: 610: 604: 596:, p. 245, 586: 582: 562: 558: 550:10.1.1.218.9262 537: 533: 521: 517: 502: 498: 482: 478: 461: 443: 411: 404: 393:predicate logic 390: 386: 372: 368: 359: 355: 350: 322:Logical atomism 303: 247:In his book on 245: 165:and the number 139:Felix Hausdorff 120: 86: 57:regress problem 17: 12: 11: 5: 651: 641: 640: 635: 630: 625: 609: 608: 602: 580: 556: 531: 515: 496: 476: 459: 441: 409: 402: 384: 366: 352: 351: 349: 346: 345: 344: 339: 334: 329: 324: 319: 314: 309: 302: 299: 270:set membership 244: 241: 240: 239: 232:point, segment 221: 203: 189: 186:multiplication 172:Arithmetic of 170: 156: 142: 119: 116: 115: 114: 98: 97: 85: 82: 33:formal systems 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 650: 639: 636: 634: 631: 629: 626: 624: 621: 620: 618: 605: 603:9780521293297 599: 595: 591: 584: 577: 573: 569: 565: 560: 551: 546: 542: 535: 528: 524: 519: 513: 509: 505: 500: 493: 489: 485: 484:Alfred Tarski 480: 473: 469: 465: 458: 454: 450: 447: 440: 436: 432: 428: 424: 421: 417: 414: 408: 401: 398: 394: 388: 381: 380: 375: 370: 363: 357: 353: 343: 340: 338: 335: 333: 330: 328: 325: 323: 320: 318: 315: 313: 310: 308: 305: 304: 298: 295: 291: 287: 283: 279: 275: 271: 267: 263: 259: 256: 255: 250: 237: 233: 229: 225: 222: 219: 215: 211: 207: 204: 201: 197: 193: 190: 187: 183: 179: 175: 171: 168: 164: 160: 157: 154: 150: 146: 143: 140: 136: 132: 128: 125: 124: 123: 111: 110: 109: 107: 103: 94: 93: 92: 90: 89:Alfred Tarski 81: 79: 75: 71: 67: 66: 60: 58: 54: 50: 46: 42: 38: 34: 30: 26: 22: 589: 583: 571: 559: 540: 534: 526: 518: 507: 499: 487: 479: 471: 467: 463: 456: 452: 448: 438: 434: 430: 426: 422: 415: 406: 399: 387: 377: 369: 356: 289: 252: 246: 235: 231: 217: 213: 174:real numbers 121: 99: 87: 73: 69: 63: 61: 36: 18: 288:of a given 264:), he used 21:mathematics 628:Set theory 617:Categories 523:Mary Tiles 490:, p. 118, 462:)", where 348:References 262:set theory 135:Mary Tiles 127:Set theory 29:philosophy 545:CiteSeerX 362:MU puzzle 268:, taking 266:relations 218:incidence 149:empty set 55:(per the 41:intuition 379:Elements 301:See also 226:: Under 208:: Under 182:addition 118:Examples 74:contains 570:(1967) 529:, p. 99 525:(2004) 506:(1959) 486:(1946) 84:Details 600:  578:118–23 547:  470:, and 374:Euclid 236:motion 234:, and 216:, and 161:: The 147:: The 72:, and 49:axioms 31:, and 153:axiom 65:point 25:logic 598:ISBN 395:as " 284:and 184:and 167:zero 70:line 35:, a 290:xRy 131:set 59:). 19:In 619:: 592:, 574:, 466:, 444:) 429:. 418:. 251:, 180:: 108:: 68:, 27:, 23:, 553:. 494:. 472:C 468:L 464:P 460:2 457:x 455:, 453:y 451:( 449:C 446:∧ 442:1 439:x 437:, 435:y 433:( 431:C 427:L 425:∈ 423:y 420:∃ 416:P 413:∈ 410:2 407:x 405:, 403:1 400:x 397:∀ 238:. 220:. 155:.

Index

mathematics
logic
philosophy
formal systems
intuition
axiomatic theory
axioms
infinite regress
regress problem
point
Hilbert's axiom system
Alfred Tarski
theory of knowledge
Gilbert de B. Robinson
Set theory
set
Mary Tiles
Felix Hausdorff
Naive set theory
empty set
axiom
Peano arithmetic
successor function
zero
real numbers
binary operations
addition
multiplication
Axiomatic systems
Alessandro Padoa

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.