Knowledge

Pragmatic maxim

Source đź“ť

731:
concepts. I did not, therefore, mean to say that acts, which are more strictly singular than anything, could constitute the purport, or adequate proper interpretation, of any symbol. I compared action to the finale of the symphony of thought, belief being a demicadence. Nobody conceives that the few bars at the end of a musical movement are the purpose of the movement. They may be called its upshot. But the figure obviously would not bear detailed application. I only mention it to show that the suspicion I myself expressed after a too hasty rereading of the forgotten magazine paper, that it expressed a stoic, that is, a nominalistic, materialistic, and utterly philistine state of thought, was quite mistaken.
37: 730:
must then have had a purpose. In point of fact it had two. One was to show that I was speaking of meaning in no other sense than that of intellectual purport. The other was to avoid all danger of being understood as attempting to explain a concept by percepts, images, schemata, or by anything but
713:
The seventh excerpt is a late reflection on the reception of pragmatism. With a sense of exasperation that is almost palpable, Peirce tries to justify the maxim of pragmatism and to correct its misreadings by pinpointing a number of false impressions that the intervening years have piled on it, and
596:
maxim, much less one that concerns itself with a routine matter of logical procedure, forms a sufficient basis for a whole philosophy. He suggests they might feel he makes pragmatism "a mere maxim of logic instead of a sublime principle of speculative philosophy." For better philosophical standing,
527:
I will restate this in other words, since ofttimes one can thus eliminate some unsuspected source of perplexity to the reader. This time it shall be in the indicative mood, as follows: The entire intellectual purport of any symbol consists in the total of all general modes of rational conduct which,
718:
analysis, he presents a veritable autopsy of the ways that the main idea of pragmatism, for all its practicality, can be murdered by a host of misdissecting disciplinarians, by what are ostensibly its most devoted followers. He proceeds here (1906) to retract a philosophical confession—in the fifth
652:
axiom which, to the present writer at the age of sixty, does not recommend itself so forcibly as it did at thirty. If it be admitted, on the contrary, that action wants an end, and that that end must be something of a general description, then the spirit of the maxim itself, which is that we must
461:
Pragmatism. The opinion that metaphysics is to be largely cleared up by the application of the following maxim for attaining clearness of apprehension: Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of
413:
It appears, then, that the rule for attaining the third grade of clearness of apprehension is as follows: Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of
640:
The fifth excerpt is useful by way of additional clarification, and is aimed to correct a variety of historical misunderstandings that arose with regard to the intended meaning of the pragmatic maxim. For a source of such misunderstanding, Peirce points to his younger self (but will retract the
562:
and provides an alternative statement of the maxim. Such reasoning, and all reasonings turn upon the idea that one who exerts certain kinds of volition will undergo, in return, certain compulsory perceptions. Now this sort of consideration—that certain lines of conduct entail certain kinds of
714:
he attempts once more to prescribe against the deleterious effects of these mistakes. Recalling the very conception and birth of pragmatism, he reviews its initial promise and its intended lot in the light of its subsequent vicissitudes and its apparent fate. Adopting the style of a
492:
The second excerpt presents the pragmatic maxim (with added emphases on forms of the word "conceive") as a recommendation to you, the addressee, on how you can clarify your conception, then restates it in the indicative, in a way that emphasizes the generalism of
591:
The fourth excerpt illustrates one of Peirce's many attempts to get the sense of the pragmatic philosophy across by rephrasing the pragmatic maxim. Introducing this version, he addresses prospective critics who do not believe a simple
574:
To ascertain the meaning of an intellectual conception one should consider what practical consequences might result from the truth of that conception—and the sum of these consequences constitute the entire meaning of the
686:
is that method of reflexion which is guided by constantly holding in view its purpose and the purpose of the ideas it analyzes, whether these ends be of the nature and uses of action or of thought. It will be seen that
793:
as "Considérer quels sont les effets pratiques que nous pensons pouvoir être produits par l'objet de notre conception. La conception de tous ces effets est la conception complète de l'objet.". Curiously, the
653:
look to the upshot of our concepts in order rightly to apprehend them, would direct us towards something different from practical facts, namely, to general ideas, as the true interpreters of our thought.
675:
A sixth excerpt is useful in stating the bearing of the pragmatic maxim on the topic of reflection, namely, that it makes all of pragmatism boil down to nothing more or less than a method of reflection.
658: 467: 444:
Peirce stated the pragmatic maxim in many different ways over the years, each of which adds its own bit of clarity or correction to their collective corpus.
405:
of logic, its function is to guide the conduct of thought toward the achievement of its purpose, advising on an optimal way of "attaining clearness of
315: 608:
is a confused form of thought whose only meaning, if it has any, lies in its tendency to enforce a corresponding practical maxim expressible as a
350: 172: 249: 754: 343: 46: 528:
conditionally upon all the possible different circumstances and desires, would ensue upon the acceptance of the symbol.
770:(ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as CP x.y for volume x, paragraph y. 823: 290: 20: 477: 423: 336: 259: 454:
as an opinion favoring application of the pragmatic maxim as a recommendation about how to clarify meaning.
406: 500:
Pragmaticism was originally enounced in the form of a maxim, as follows: Consider what effects that might
419: 544: 85: 736: 581: 763: 323: 627:
Pragmatism as a Principle and Method of Right Thinking: The 1903 Harvard 'Lectures on Pragmatism',
300: 128: 702: 390: 275: 163: 28: 537: 790: 782: 604:
Pragmatism is the principle that every theoretical judgment expressible in a sentence in the
310: 663: 609: 472: 398: 305: 138: 108: 92: 719:
excerpt (above)—which he wrote in 1902 about his 1878 original presentation of pragmatism.
8: 818: 448:
The first excerpt appears in the form of a dictionary entry, intended as a definition of
227: 65: 759: 382: 201: 153: 402: 394: 123: 789:, which published it in its Volume VII in January 1879. There the maxim appeared on 295: 118: 767: 613: 605: 285: 113: 813: 693: 280: 254: 807: 597:
he endeavors to put pragmatism into the same form of a philosophical theorem:
409:". Here is its original 1878 statement in English when it was not yet named: 222: 196: 143: 697:
but is a method of reflexion having for its purpose to render ideas clear.
377: 186: 181: 75: 148: 70: 36: 450: 370: 133: 55: 593: 239: 233: 191: 158: 622: 648:
The doctrine appears to assume that the end of man is action - a
244: 217: 682:
The study of philosophy consists, therefore, in reflexion, and
649: 439: 781:
The article containing it was originally written in French as
386: 462:
these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.
798:
version omits the article's last one and a half paragraphs.
567:. This justifies the maxim as a practical belief, that: 641:
confession as itself mistaken—see the seventh excerpt).
621:(Peirce, 1903, from the lectures on Pragmatism, CP 558:The third excerpt puts a gloss on the meaning of a 430:, v. 12, pp. 286–302. Reprinted widely, including 805: 726:This employment five times over of derivates of 532:(Peirce, 1905, from "Issues of Pragmaticism" in 344: 440:Seven ways of looking at the pragmatic maxim 755:Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce 432:Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce 351: 337: 484:v. 12, pp. 286-302. Reprinted in CP 5.2). 476:, including quote of himself from 1878, " 664:Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology 473:Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology 806: 516:of those effects is the whole of your 536:v. XV, n. 4, pp. 481-499, see p. 481 119:Entitative graph in Qualitative logic 563:inevitable experiences—is called a 13: 783:"Comment rendre nos idĂ©es claires" 14: 835: 35: 434:(CP) v. 5, paragraphs 388–410.) 291:Charles Santiago Sanders Peirce 775: 1: 746: 504:have practical bearings you 7: 612:having its apodosis in the 478:How to Make Our Ideas Clear 424:How to Make Our Ideas Clear 210:Miscellaneous contributions 10: 840: 667:. Reprinted CP 5.3, 1902). 550:. Reprinted in CP 5.438.). 250:Classification of sciences 766:(eds.), Vols. 7–8, 659:Pragmatic and Pragmatism 468:Pragmatic and Pragmatism 395:normative recommendation 324:Peirce Geodetic Monument 565:practical consideration 482:Popular Science Monthly 428:Popular Science Monthly 301:Christine Ladd-Franklin 129:Functional completeness 824:Charles Sanders Peirce 742: 708: 670: 618: 577: 553: 522: 487: 437: 391:Charles Sanders Peirce 276:Joseph Morton Ransdell 260:Quincuncial projection 164:Type-token distinction 29:Charles Sanders Peirce 758:, Volumes 1–6, 724: 680: 657:(Peirce, 1902, from " 646: 602: 572: 525: 498: 459: 411: 311:The Metaphysical Club 610:conditional sentence 512:to have. Then, your 508:the objects of your 399:regulative principle 367:, also known as the 306:Victoria, Lady Welby 139:Logic of information 109:Continuous predicate 93:Community of inquiry 796:Revue Philosophique 787:Revue Philosophique 66:Abductive reasoning 760:Charles Hartshorne 701:(Peirce, 1902, CP 580:(Peirce, 1905, CP 202:Universal rhetoric 154:Second-order logic 86:as theory of truth 633:v. 2, pp. 134-5.) 560:practical bearing 403:normative science 361: 360: 124:Existential graph 831: 799: 779: 631:Essential Peirce 547:Internet Archive 466:(Peirce, 1902, " 353: 346: 339: 296:Roberta Kevelson 39: 16: 15: 839: 838: 834: 833: 832: 830: 829: 828: 804: 803: 802: 780: 776: 768:Arthur W. Burks 749: 737:CP 5.402 note 3 735:(Peirce, 1906, 629:p. 110, and in 614:imperative mood 606:indicative mood 442: 393:. Serving as a 365:pragmatic maxim 357: 286:Juliette Peirce 173:Semiotic theory 58:in epistemology 12: 11: 5: 837: 827: 826: 821: 816: 801: 800: 773: 772: 771: 752:Peirce, C.S., 748: 745: 744: 743: 741: 740: 721: 720: 710: 709: 707: 706: 694:Weltanschauung 677: 676: 672: 671: 669: 668: 643: 642: 637: 636: 635: 634: 599: 598: 588: 587: 586: 585: 569: 568: 555: 554: 552: 551: 523: 520:of the object. 495: 494: 489: 488: 486: 485: 456: 455: 441: 438: 436: 435: 389:formulated by 359: 358: 356: 355: 348: 341: 333: 330: 329: 328: 327: 320: 319: 318: 308: 303: 298: 293: 288: 283: 281:Allan Marquand 278: 270: 269: 265: 264: 263: 262: 257: 255:Listing number 252: 247: 242: 237: 230: 225: 220: 212: 211: 207: 206: 205: 204: 199: 194: 189: 184: 176: 175: 169: 168: 167: 166: 161: 156: 151: 146: 141: 136: 131: 126: 121: 116: 111: 103: 102: 98: 97: 96: 95: 90: 89: 88: 83: 73: 68: 60: 59: 52: 51: 50: 49: 41: 40: 32: 31: 25: 24: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 836: 825: 822: 820: 817: 815: 812: 811: 809: 797: 792: 788: 784: 778: 774: 769: 765: 761: 757: 756: 751: 750: 738: 734: 733: 732: 729: 723: 722: 717: 712: 711: 704: 700: 699: 698: 696: 695: 690: 685: 679: 678: 674: 673: 666: 665: 660: 656: 655: 654: 651: 645: 644: 639: 638: 632: 628: 624: 620: 619: 617: 615: 611: 607: 601: 600: 595: 590: 589: 583: 579: 578: 576: 571: 570: 566: 561: 557: 556: 549: 548: 542: 541: 535: 531: 530: 529: 524: 521: 519: 515: 511: 507: 503: 497: 496: 491: 490: 483: 479: 475: 474: 469: 465: 464: 463: 458: 457: 453: 452: 447: 446: 445: 433: 429: 425: 421: 417: 416: 415: 410: 408: 404: 400: 396: 392: 388: 384: 380: 379: 373: 372: 366: 354: 349: 347: 342: 340: 335: 334: 332: 331: 326: 325: 321: 317: 314: 313: 312: 309: 307: 304: 302: 299: 297: 294: 292: 289: 287: 284: 282: 279: 277: 274: 273: 272: 271: 267: 266: 261: 258: 256: 253: 251: 248: 246: 243: 241: 238: 236: 235: 231: 229: 226: 224: 223:Bell triangle 221: 219: 216: 215: 214: 213: 209: 208: 203: 200: 198: 197:Sign relation 195: 193: 190: 188: 185: 183: 180: 179: 178: 177: 174: 171: 170: 165: 162: 160: 157: 155: 152: 150: 147: 145: 144:Logical graph 142: 140: 137: 135: 132: 130: 127: 125: 122: 120: 117: 115: 112: 110: 107: 106: 105: 104: 100: 99: 94: 91: 87: 84: 82: 79: 78: 77: 74: 72: 69: 67: 64: 63: 62: 61: 57: 54: 53: 48: 45: 44: 43: 42: 38: 34: 33: 30: 27: 26: 22: 18: 17: 795: 786: 785:in 1877 for 777: 753: 727: 725: 715: 692: 688: 683: 681: 662: 647: 630: 626: 603: 573: 564: 559: 546: 540:Google Books 539: 533: 526: 517: 513: 509: 505: 501: 499: 481: 471: 460: 449: 443: 431: 427: 414:the object. 412: 407:apprehension 378:pragmaticism 375: 368: 364: 362: 322: 268:Biographical 232: 187:Interpretant 182:Indexicality 114:Peirce's law 80: 76:Pragmaticism 47:Bibliography 716:post mortem 703:5.13 note 1 575:conception. 502:conceivably 493:pragmatism: 418:(Peirce on 149:Logical NOR 71:Fallibilism 819:Pragmatism 808:Categories 764:Paul Weiss 747:References 689:pragmatism 684:pragmatism 625:, also in 534:The Monist 518:conception 514:conception 510:conception 451:pragmatism 371:pragmatism 228:Categories 134:Logic gate 56:Pragmatism 728:concipere 691:is not a 661:" in the 594:heuristic 470:" in the 376:maxim of 369:maxim of 240:Synechism 506:conceive 234:Phaneron 192:Semiosis 159:Trikonic 81:as maxim 21:a series 19:Part of 650:stoical 401:in the 381:, is a 374:or the 245:Tychism 218:Agapism 420:p. 293 814:Logic 791:p. 48 480:" in 397:or a 387:logic 383:maxim 101:Logic 762:and 623:5.18 545:via 543:and 538:via 422:of " 363:The 316:book 582:5.9 426:", 385:of 810:: 739:). 705:). 584:.) 23:on 616:. 352:e 345:t 338:v

Index

a series
Charles Sanders Peirce

Bibliography
Pragmatism
Abductive reasoning
Fallibilism
Pragmaticism
as maxim
as theory of truth
Community of inquiry
Continuous predicate
Peirce's law
Entitative graph in Qualitative logic
Existential graph
Functional completeness
Logic gate
Logic of information
Logical graph
Logical NOR
Second-order logic
Trikonic
Type-token distinction
Semiotic theory
Indexicality
Interpretant
Semiosis
Sign relation
Universal rhetoric
Agapism

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑