Knowledge

Metagame analysis

Source 📝

200:
This analysis procedure shows that the credibility of threats and promises (sanctions and improvements) is of importance in metagame analysis. A threat or promise, one that the stakeholder prefers to carry out for its own sake, is inherently credible. Sometimes a stakeholder may want to make credible
186:
preferred to the particular scenario, making it not worthwhile for that stakeholder to have helped with the improvement. The general "law of stability" to be used in scenario analysis is: for a scenario to be stable, it is necessary for each credible improvement to be deterred by a credible sanction (
185:
Identify all sanctions that exist to deter the unilateral improvements. A sanction against an improvement is a possible reaction to an improvement by the stakeholders who were not involved in the improvement. It is such that the stakeholder who was involved in the improvement finds the sanction not
177:
Choose a particular scenario to analyse for stability. A scenario is stable if "each stakeholder expects to do its part and expects others to do theirs." Note that stable scenarios are accepted by all stakeholders, but that acceptance does not need to be voluntary. There may be more than one stable
195:
Draw a strategic map, laying out all the threats and promises stakeholders can make to try to stabilise the situation at scenarios they prefer. Strategic maps are diagrams in which scenarios are shown by balloons, with arrows from one balloon to another representing unilateral improvements. Dotted
147:
The present scenario, which may differ from the Status Quo as it incorporates the intentions that are expressed by the stakeholders to change their plans; the Status Quo necessarily remains the same, but the present scenario may change as stakeholders interact and influence each other's
181:
Identify all unilateral improvements for stakeholders and subsets of stakeholders from the particular scenario. These are all the scenarios that are both preferred by all members of a certain subset and 'reachable' by them alone changing their selection of individual
131:
If the set of feasible scenarios is too large to be analysed in full, some combinations may be eliminated because the analyst judges them to be not worth considering. When doing so, the analyst should take care to preserve these particular types of scenarios
256:
The manager as politician and general: the metagame approach to analysing cooperation and conflict. In: Rosenhead J (ed) Rational analysis for a problematic world: problem structuring methods for complexity, uncertainty and
201:
an 'involuntary' threat or promise, to use this to move the situation in the desired direction. Such threats and promises can be made credible in three basic ways: preference change, irrationality, and deceit (
50:
exist, and who has the power to control the course of events. The practical application of metagame theory is based on the analysis of options method, first applied to study problems like the strategic
157:
between two stakeholders, defined as scenarios that, while not the position of either, are preferred by both to the other's position. A compromise does not necessarily have to involve all stakeholders.
92:
The dependencies between options should typically be formulated as "option X can only be implemented if option Y is also implemented", or "options Y and Z are mutually exclusive". The result is a
26:
in which participants try to realise their objectives by means of the options available to them. The subsequent meta-analysis of this game gives insight in possible strategies and their outcome.
169:
The next step in the metagame analysis consists of the actual analysis of the scenarios generated so far. This analysis centres around stability and is broken down in the following four steps (
128:. Conversely, the dependencies between options will reduce the number of scenarios, because they rule out those containing logically or physically impossible combinations of options. 151:
The positions of different stakeholders, being the scenarios they would like others to agree to. Similar to the present scenario, positions may change through interaction.
213:
Metagame analysis is still used as a technique in its own right. However it has been further developed in distinct ways as the basis of more recent approaches:
196:
arrows from improvement arrows to balloons represent sanctions by which the improvements may be deterred, thus changing the destination of the improvement arrow.
124:
possible outcomes. As the number of stakeholders and the number of the options they have increase, the number of scenarios will increase steeply due to a
192:
Steps 1 to 3 need to be repeated to analyse some additional scenarios. When a number of scenarios have been analysed, one can proceed to the next step:
46:
in terms of decision issues, and stakeholders who may exert different options to gain control over these issues. The analysis reveals what likely
264: 242: 160:
Conflict points, defined as scenarios that stakeholders might move to in trying to force others to accept their positions.
285: 67:
Metagame analysis proceeds in three phases: analysis of options, scenario development, and scenario analysis.
38:
on a non-quantitative basis, hoping that it would thereby make more practical and intuitive sense (
306:
Proceedings of the 34th Conference of the International Simulation and Gaming Association (ISAGA)
125: 220: 34:
Metagame theory was developed by Nigel Howard in the 1960s as a reconstruction of mathematical
278:
Games in a world of infrastructures. Simulation-Games for Research, Learning, and Intervention
56: 43: 329: 85:
Make an inventory of policy options by means of which the stakeholders control the issues.
8: 178:
scenario, the stability of a scenario may change, and unstable scenarios can also happen.
298: 281: 260: 238: 104:
The possible outcomes of the game, based on the combination of options, are called
82:
Identify the stakeholders who control the issues, either directly or indirectly.
323: 75:
The first phase of analysis of options consists of the following four steps:
35: 299:"Developing 'playable metagames' for participatory stakeholder analysis" 154: 141: 52: 105: 93: 47: 235:
Paradoxes of Rationality: Games, Metagames, and Political Behavior
79:
Structure the problem by identifying the issues to be decided.
23: 144:, representing the future as it was previously expected. 88:
Determine the dependencies between the policy options.
96:
model, which can then be analysed in different ways.
22:
involves framing a problem situation as a strategic
296: 275: 321: 116:who have Oi options (i = 1, ..., N), there are O 42:, pp. xi). Metagame analysis reflects on a 276:Veeneman, Wijnand; Igor Mayer, eds. (2002). 237:. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. 259:. Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons. 108:. In theory, a game with N stakeholders s 297:Bots, P. W. G.; Hermans, L. M. (2003). 99: 322: 253: 232: 202: 187: 170: 133: 70: 39: 164: 16:Problem solving as a strategic game 13: 280:. Delft, The Netherlands: Eburon. 14: 341: 208: 1: 226: 7: 10: 346: 62: 29: 126:combinatorial explosion 254:Howard, Nigel (1989). 233:Howard, Nigel (1971). 221:confrontation analysis 173:, pp. 248–255): 57:nuclear proliferation 136:, pp. 243 ff): 100:Scenario development 71:Analysis of options 266:978-0-471-92286-5 244:978-0-262-58237-7 205:, pp. 257). 165:Scenario analysis 20:Metagame analysis 337: 316: 314: 313: 303: 291: 270: 248: 345: 344: 340: 339: 338: 336: 335: 334: 320: 319: 311: 309: 301: 288: 267: 245: 229: 217:the graph model 211: 191: 190:, pp. 251) 167: 123: 119: 115: 111: 102: 73: 65: 32: 17: 12: 11: 5: 343: 333: 332: 318: 317: 308:. Chiba, Japan 293: 292: 286: 272: 271: 265: 250: 249: 243: 228: 225: 224: 223: 218: 210: 207: 198: 197: 193: 183: 179: 166: 163: 162: 161: 158: 152: 149: 145: 121: 117: 113: 109: 101: 98: 90: 89: 86: 83: 80: 72: 69: 64: 61: 31: 28: 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 342: 331: 328: 327: 325: 307: 300: 295: 294: 289: 287:90-5166-924-0 283: 279: 274: 273: 268: 262: 258: 252: 251: 246: 240: 236: 231: 230: 222: 219: 216: 215: 214: 206: 204: 194: 189: 184: 180: 176: 175: 174: 172: 159: 156: 153: 150: 146: 143: 139: 138: 137: 135: 129: 127: 107: 97: 95: 87: 84: 81: 78: 77: 76: 68: 60: 58: 54: 49: 45: 41: 37: 27: 25: 21: 310:. Retrieved 305: 277: 255: 234: 212: 199: 168: 130: 103: 91: 74: 66: 33: 19: 18: 330:Game theory 209:Development 203:Howard 1989 188:Howard 1989 171:Howard 1989 155:Compromises 134:Howard 1989 40:Howard 1971 36:game theory 312:2007-09-22 227:References 142:Status Quo 106:scenarios 53:arms race 48:scenarios 324:Category 257:conflict 182:options. 112:, ..., s 94:metagame 44:problem 284:  263:  241:  148:plans. 120:×...×O 63:Method 30:Origin 302:(PDF) 282:ISBN 261:ISBN 239:ISBN 140:The 55:and 24:game 326:: 304:. 59:. 315:. 290:. 269:. 247:. 132:( 122:N 118:1 114:N 110:1

Index

game
game theory
Howard 1971
problem
scenarios
arms race
nuclear proliferation
metagame
scenarios
combinatorial explosion
Howard 1989
Status Quo
Compromises
Howard 1989
Howard 1989
Howard 1989
confrontation analysis
ISBN
978-0-262-58237-7
ISBN
978-0-471-92286-5
ISBN
90-5166-924-0
"Developing 'playable metagames' for participatory stakeholder analysis"
Category
Game theory

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.