Knowledge

Explication

Source 📝

202:
take the place of the first (or the term proposed for it) the explicatum. The explicandum may belong to everyday language or to a previous stage in the development of scientific language. The explicatum must be given by explicit rules for its use, for example, by a definition which incorporates it into a well-constructed system of scientific either logicomathematical or empirical concepts."
176:
that is, the rather naive understandings that most of us have about how life, the universe, and everything work." Explications of abstract concepts, such as color, do not list any scientific facts about the object or concrete definitions. Instead, the explications use comparisons and examples from the real world.
201:
As argued by Carnap (1950), in science and philosophy, "explication consists in transforming a given more or less inexact concept into an exact one or, rather, in replacing the first by the second. We call the given concept (or the term used for it) the explicandum, and the exact concept proposed to
95:
An explication in the Carnapian sense is purely stipulative, and thus a subclass of normative definitions. Hence, an explication can not be true or false, just more or less suitable for its purpose. (Cf. Rorty's argument about the purpose and value of philosophy in Rorty (2003), "A pragmatist view of
175:
Explications in the Natural Semantic Metalanguage are neither exact dictionary definitions, nor encyclopedic explanations of a concept. They often differ slightly depending upon the personal experiences of the person writing them. In this way, they can be said to "rely heavily on 'folk theories,'
99:
Examples of inexact daily life concepts in need of explication are our concepts of cause and of conditionals. Our daily life concept of cause does not distinguish between necessary causes, sufficient causes, complete causes etc. Each of these more precise concepts is an explication of our natural
119:
Others' reviews of Carnap's argument offer additional insights about the nature of explication. In particular, Bonolio's paper (2003) "Kant’s Explication and Carnap’s Explication: The Redde Rationem", and Maher's (2007) "Explication defended", add weight to the argument that explication is an
107:
for propositions of the form "If p, then q" for situations where "p" is true. (Most of us probably don't have any clear intuitions regarding the truth conditions of the sentence "If I go out in the sun, I will get sunburned" in situations where I never go out in the sun.) An explication of the
162:
X feels happy = sometimes someone thinks something like this: something good happened to something I wanted this I don't want other things now because of this, someone feels something good X feels like this
83:. Explication can be regarded as a scientific process which transforms and replaces "an inexact prescientific concept" (which Carnap calls the explicandum), with a "new exact concept" (which he calls the explicatum). A description and 128:
The word "explicate" is a verb referring to the process of explicating. The word "explication" is a noun referring to the outcome of that process: the explicative work itself. As conceptual clarity is an important element of
167:
What sets the Natural Semantic Metalanguage Theory's explications apart from previous theories, is that these explications can fit into natural language, even if it sounds very awkward. For example:
235:, and explication per se, is an interpretative process where the resulting new knowledge, new insights or new meanings, are open to subsequent debate and disaffirmation by others. 229:
In this process, explication often involves a line-by-line or episode-by-episode commentary on what is going on in a text. While initially this might seem reasonably innocuous,
87:
of the nature and impact of the new explicit knowledge is usually called an "explication". The new explicit knowledge draws on, and is an improvement upon, previous knowledge.
116:
Carnap's argument provides a helpful foundation in understanding and clarifying the nature and value of explication in defining and describing "new" knowledge.
38:) is the process of drawing out the meaning of something which is not clearly defined, so as to make explicit what is currently left implicit. The term 96:
contemporary analytic philosophy", in Egginton, W. and Sandbothe, M. (Eds), The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy, SUNY Press, New York, NY.)
145:
theory, explications are semantic representations of vocabulary. These explications are made up of a very limited set of words called
301: 360: 369: 205:
In this context, 'explication' is now regarded as "an appropriate methodology for formal philosophy". (Maher, 2007).
133:, it is important to use words according to their proper definitions so as to avoid causing unnecessary confusion. 142: 388: 17: 393: 324: 231: 214: 194: 8: 252: 130: 43: 403: 398: 299:
Bonolio, G. (2003). "Kant’s Explication and Carnap’s Explication: The Redde Rationem",
209: 47: 320: 108:
conditional will also specify truth conditions for situations where "p" is not true.
104: 373: 146: 54:
was the first to coin the term in an analytic philosophical approach in his book
31: 66:
when referring to the analysis and criticism of different forms of literature.
219: 59: 367:
The Close Reading of Poetry: A Practical Introduction and Guide to Explication
329: 382: 366: 341: 223: 80: 51: 179: 79:
In analytic philosophy, the concept of explication was first developed by
84: 315:
Harrison, S. E. (2006). "Explication without words: A composer's view",
222:), where additional understandings and meanings are derived from the " 149:
which are considered to have universal meaning across all languages.
355: 336: 123: 212:, the term 'explication' is used as a proxy for the term 285:. Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics. pp. 69–73. 345:, Volume 86, Number 2, July 2007, pp. 331–341. 69: 380: 330:Introducing explication. Online since April 2013 120:appropriate methodology for formal philosophy. 111: 305:Vol. 43, No. 3, Issue 171, pp. 289–298. 90: 152:An example of an explication of the word 312:, University of Chicago Press, Illinois. 171:The clown looks The clown looks like . 136: 14: 381: 319:, August, Vol.13 (3), pp. 59–63. 280: 302:International Philosophical Quarterly 276: 274: 272: 58:, while the term is supplanted with 361:Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy 103:Natural language will only specify 24: 310:Logical foundations of probability 226:" of (say) a poem, novel or play. 56:Logical Foundations of Probability 25: 415: 349: 269: 245: 70:Carnap's notion of explication 13: 1: 293: 143:natural semantic metalanguage 124:Use of the word "explication" 112:Reviews of Carnap's argument 7: 253:"Definition of EXPLICATION" 10: 420: 74: 281:Murphy, M. Lynne (2010). 198:have different meanings. 317:Organisations and People 238: 184:, and literary criticism 169: 160: 91:On explication and truth 257:www.merriam-webster.com 337:"Explication defended" 35: 232:explication de texte 215:explication de texte 195:explication de texte 182:explication de texte 137:Semantic explication 64:Explication de Texte 389:Analytic philosophy 308:Carnap, R. (1950). 131:analytic philosophy 44:analytic philosophy 394:Literary criticism 372:2013-04-06 at the 210:literary criticism 100:concept of cause. 48:literary criticism 335:Maher, P. (2007) 16:(Redirected from 411: 287: 286: 278: 267: 266: 264: 263: 249: 208:By contrast, in 105:truth conditions 42:is used in both 21: 419: 418: 414: 413: 412: 410: 409: 408: 379: 378: 374:Wayback Machine 358:article in the 352: 296: 291: 290: 283:Lexical Meaning 279: 270: 261: 259: 251: 250: 246: 241: 186: 173: 172: 165: 164: 147:semantic primes 139: 126: 114: 93: 77: 72: 23: 22: 15: 12: 11: 5: 417: 407: 406: 401: 396: 391: 377: 376: 364: 351: 350:External links 348: 347: 346: 333: 327: 313: 306: 295: 292: 289: 288: 268: 243: 242: 240: 237: 220:Gustave Lanson 185: 178: 170: 161: 138: 135: 125: 122: 113: 110: 92: 89: 76: 73: 71: 68: 60:Gustave Lanson 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 416: 405: 402: 400: 397: 395: 392: 390: 387: 386: 384: 375: 371: 368: 365: 363: 362: 357: 354: 353: 344: 343: 342:Studia Logica 338: 334: 331: 328: 326: 322: 318: 314: 311: 307: 304: 303: 298: 297: 284: 277: 275: 273: 258: 254: 248: 244: 236: 234: 233: 227: 225: 224:close reading 221: 218:(proposed by 217: 216: 211: 206: 203: 199: 197: 196: 191: 183: 180:Explication, 177: 168: 159: 158: 155: 150: 148: 144: 134: 132: 121: 117: 109: 106: 101: 97: 88: 86: 82: 81:Rudolf Carnap 67: 65: 61: 57: 53: 52:Rudolf Carnap 49: 45: 41: 37: 33: 29: 19: 359: 340: 316: 309: 300: 282: 260:. Retrieved 256: 247: 230: 228: 213: 207: 204: 200: 193: 189: 187: 181: 174: 166: 156: 153: 151: 140: 127: 118: 115: 102: 98: 94: 78: 63: 55: 39: 27: 26: 18:Explications 356:Explication 190:explication 85:explanation 62:’s idea of 40:explication 36:Explikation 28:Explication 383:Categories 294:References 262:2021-01-21 188:The terms 404:Semiotics 399:Semantics 325:1350-6269 370:Archived 141:In the 75:Summary 323:  32:German 239:Notes 154:happy 321:ISSN 192:and 46:and 385:: 339:, 271:^ 255:. 50:. 34:: 332:. 265:. 157:: 30:( 20:)

Index

Explications
German
analytic philosophy
literary criticism
Rudolf Carnap
Gustave Lanson
Rudolf Carnap
explanation
truth conditions
analytic philosophy
natural semantic metalanguage
semantic primes
explication de texte
literary criticism
explication de texte
Gustave Lanson
close reading
explication de texte
"Definition of EXPLICATION"



International Philosophical Quarterly
ISSN
1350-6269
Introducing explication. Online since April 2013
"Explication defended"
Studia Logica
Explication
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.