Knowledge

A posteriori necessity

Source 📝

106:(P2) If both names designate rigidly, they designate the same object (Venus) in every possible world in which it exists. Therefore (by the definition of 'necessary') 'Hesperus = Phosphorus' is necessarily true. If it is the case that in all possible worlds the identity claim "Hesperus is Phosphorus" is true, the statement is necessary. 101:(P1) 'Hesperus' is a proper name that refers to the evening star. 'Phosphorus' is also a proper name and it refers to the morning star. But the evening star and the morning star are the same planetary body (Venus). So both names designate Venus. 205:
comments on the significance of Kripke's counter-examples: "Since Kant there has been a big split between philosophers who thought that all necessary truths were analytic and philosophers who thought that some necessary truths were synthetic
159:
necessity existing would make the distinction between a prioricity, analyticity, and necessity harder to discern because they were previously thought to be largely separated from the
372: 111:(P3) The fact that Hesperus is Phosphorus was discovered by empirical observation, and it could not have been discovered 367: 377: 228: 307: 284: 233: 47: 42: 32: 196: 210:. But none of these philosophers thought that a (metaphysically) necessary truth could fail to be 46:
knowledge can be necessary. It draws on a number of philosophical concepts such as necessity, the
27: 223: 92: 75: 70: 73:. The transcript of these lectures was then compiled and assembled into his seminal book, 8: 357: 362: 238: 51: 37: 174: 351: 248: 202: 243: 66: 23: 155:
is among the most important philosophical works of the 20th century.
82: 30:, that some statements of which we must acquire knowledge 40:. It challenges previously widespread belief that only 124:(C) Therefore, it is possible for knowledge obtained 329:Putnam, Hilary (1975). "The Meaning of 'Meaning'". 349: 331:Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 272:. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. 310:. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 287:. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 282: 65:It was first introduced by philosopher 373:Concepts in the philosophy of language 350: 328: 305: 267: 163:, the synthetic, and the contingent. 97:Here is an overview of the argument: 283:LaPorte, Joseph (24 October 2006). 13: 69:in his 1970 series of lectures at 14: 389: 306:Vaidya, Anand (5 December 2007). 147: 322: 308:"The Epistemology of Modality" 299: 276: 261: 1: 254: 229:Descriptivist theory of names 7: 217: 136:necessary truths include: " 10: 394: 234:Causal theory of reference 90: 48:causal theory of reference 115:. Therefore, it is known 368:Concepts in epistemology 268:Kripke, Saul A. (1980). 378:Concepts in metaphysics 28:philosophy of language 224:Necessity of identity 93:Necessity of identity 91:Further information: 270:Naming and Necessity 153:Naming and Necessity 76:Naming and Necessity 71:Princeton University 285:"Rigid Designators" 132:Other instances of 83:Main argument for 385: 339: 338: 326: 320: 319: 317: 315: 303: 297: 296: 294: 292: 280: 274: 273: 265: 239:Rigid designator 143: 128:to be necessary. 38:necessarily true 393: 392: 388: 387: 386: 384: 383: 382: 348: 347: 345: 343: 342: 327: 323: 313: 311: 304: 300: 290: 288: 281: 277: 266: 262: 257: 220: 150: 141: 137: 95: 89: 22:is a thesis in 12: 11: 5: 391: 381: 380: 375: 370: 365: 360: 341: 340: 321: 298: 275: 259: 258: 256: 253: 252: 251: 246: 241: 236: 231: 226: 219: 216: 180:is necessary. 149: 146: 139: 130: 129: 121: 120: 108: 107: 103: 102: 88: 81: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 390: 379: 376: 374: 371: 369: 366: 364: 361: 359: 356: 355: 353: 346: 336: 332: 325: 309: 302: 286: 279: 271: 264: 260: 250: 247: 245: 242: 240: 237: 235: 232: 230: 227: 225: 222: 221: 215: 213: 209: 204: 203:Hilary Putnam 200: 198: 194: 190: 186: 181: 179: 176: 173: 169: 164: 162: 158: 154: 145: 135: 127: 123: 122: 118: 114: 110: 109: 105: 104: 100: 99: 98: 94: 86: 80: 78: 77: 72: 68: 63: 62:distinction. 61: 57: 53: 49: 45: 44: 39: 35: 34: 29: 25: 21: 19: 344: 334: 330: 324: 312:. Retrieved 301: 289:. Retrieved 278: 269: 263: 211: 207: 201: 192: 189:a posteriori 188: 184: 182: 177: 171: 167: 165: 161:a posteriori 160: 157:A posteriori 156: 152: 151: 148:Significance 134:a posteriori 133: 131: 126:a posteriori 125: 117:a posteriori 116: 112: 96: 85:a posteriori 84: 74: 64: 60:a posteriori 59: 55: 41: 33:a posteriori 31: 18:A posteriori 17: 16: 15: 144:is water". 67:Saul Kripke 24:metaphysics 352:Categories 337:: 131–193. 255:References 197:contingent 54:, and the 358:Necessity 249:Necessity 87:necessity 36:are also 20:necessity 363:A priori 314:5 August 291:5 August 244:Modality 218:See also 212:a priori 208:a priori 172:a priori 113:a priori 56:a priori 52:rigidity 43:a priori 26:and the 316:2016 293:2016 191:iff 183:(b) 166:(a) 214:." 195:is 187:is 175:iff 170:is 354:: 333:. 199:. 79:. 50:, 335:7 318:. 295:. 193:P 185:P 178:P 168:P 142:O 140:2 138:H 119:. 58:–

Index

metaphysics
philosophy of language
a posteriori
necessarily true
a priori
causal theory of reference
rigidity
Saul Kripke
Princeton University
Naming and Necessity
Necessity of identity
iff
contingent
Hilary Putnam
Necessity of identity
Descriptivist theory of names
Causal theory of reference
Rigid designator
Modality
Necessity
"Rigid Designators"
"The Epistemology of Modality"
Categories
Necessity
A priori
Concepts in epistemology
Concepts in the philosophy of language
Concepts in metaphysics

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.