Knowledge

Perfectionism (philosophy)

Source đź“ť

126:
William Rothman summarizes the idea, Cavell "takes it to be our primary task as human beings—at once our deepest wish, whether or not we know this about ourselves, and our moral obligation—to become more fully human, to realize our humanity in our lives in the world, which always requires the simultaneous acknowledgment of the humanity of others (our acknowledgment of them, and theirs of us)."
59:
properties to a high degree or realizes what is central to human nature. Different versions of the theory may disagree about what the relevant properties are and so disagree about the content of the good life. But they share the foundational idea that what is good, ultimately, is the development of human nature.
58:
This moral theory starts from an account of the good life, or the intrinsically desirable life. And it characterizes this life in a distinctive way. Certain properties, it says, constitute human nature or are definitive of humanity—they make humans human. The good life, it then says, develops these
89:
develops the concept of moral perfectionism as the idea that there is an unattained but attainable self that one ought to strive to reach. Moral perfectionists believe that the ancient questions such as "Am I living as I am supposed to?" make all the difference in the world and they describe the
275:
essays. According to the view he advanced in the 1869 publication, "Culture is a study of perfection". He further wrote that: " seeks to do away with classes; to make the best that has been thought and known in the world current everywhere; to make all men live in an atmosphere of sweetness and
283:
The whole scope of the essay is to recommend culture as the great help out of our present difficulties; culture being a pursuit of our total perfection by means of getting to know, on all the matters which most concern us, the best which has been thought and said in the world, and, through this
125:
view that the good action is that which will cause the least harm, or the greatest good for the greatest number. For Cavell, moral perfectionism is an outlook or register of thought, a way of thinking about morality expressed thematically in certain works of philosophy, literature and film. As
210:
address in their witty give- and-take, for example, are, as Cavell puts it, "formulated less well by questions concerning what they ought to do, what it would be best or right for them to do, than by the question how they shall live their lives, what kind of persons they aspire to be."
245:
was of the view that there are no universal parameters of perfection. Individuals and cultures choose those values that, for them, represent the ideal of perfection. For example, one individual may view education as leading perfection, while to another beauty is the highest ideal.
258:
is the goal. If I were condemned to choose between a humanity materially happy, glutted after the manner of a flock of sheep in a field, and a humanity existing in misery, but from which emanated, here and there, some eternal truth, it is on the latter my choice would fall.
284:
knowledge, turning a stream of fresh and free thought upon our stock notions and habits, which we now follow staunchly but mechanically, vainly imagining that there is a virtue in following them staunchly which makes up for the mischief of following them mechanically.
192:" and "the melodrama of the unknown woman". Cavell's argument is that these films are illustrative of moral perfectionism (and, more specifically, Emersonian perfectionism).The moral questions couples in remarriage comedies like 90:
commitment we ought to have in ways that seem, but are not, impossibly demanding. We do so because it is only in the keeping such an "impossible" view in mind that one can strive for one's "unattained but attainable self."
253:
The true role of collective existence ... is to learn, to discover, to know. Eating, drinking, sleeping, living, in a word, is a mere accessory. In this respect, we are not distinguished from the brute.
239:). While the individual is responsible for living a virtuous life, the state should be limited to the regulation of human coexistence. 440:
Immanuel Kant: Ăśber den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht fĂĽr die Praxis, AA VIII, 273-314, hier 291
489: 109:
perfectionism," the form of moral perfectionism he embraces and defends, not as a theory of moral philosophy comparable to
425: 400: 375: 76:). He taught that politics and political structures should promote the good life among individuals; because the 206: 227:
in all its forms. A society devoted to perfectionist principles may not produce happy citizens—far from it.
68:
Perfectionism, as a moral theory, has a long history and has been addressed by influential philosophers.
20: 499: 114: 82:
can best promote the good life, it should be adopted over other forms of social organization.
194: 314: 189: 393:
Must We Kill the Thing We Love? Emersonian Perfectionism and the Films of Alfred Hitchcock
8: 494: 272: 175: 163: 147: 143: 264: 98: 467: 421: 396: 371: 364: 97:(2005), based on a lecture course called "Moral Perfectionism" that he first gave at 39: 294: 180: 151: 118: 200: 329: 268: 224: 117:) by which we can rationally determine whether an action is right or wrong, or 102: 86: 162:, endorsing Cavell's understanding of moral perfectionism and such artists as 483: 449: 302: 242: 228: 155: 139: 110: 171: 51: 43: 31: 324: 232: 185: 167: 122: 319: 159: 130:
pairs chapters on major philosophers in the Western tradition, such as
106: 73: 255: 220: 135: 69: 366:
Cities of Words: Pedagogical Letters on a Register of the Moral Life
95:
Cities of Words: Pedagogical Letters on a Register of the Moral Life
188:) a member of the classical Hollywood genres; what he called "the 298: 105:
characterizes moral perfectionism in general, and what he calls "
469:
Culture and anarchy; an essay in political and social criticism
420:. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. p. 354. 113:’s deontological view that there is a universal moral law (the 27: 131: 78: 47: 297:
argues that rational perfectionism is, or should be, the
235:, which he denied for the sake of a "patriotic" state ( 219:
Perfection means more than—or something different from—
395:. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. p. 4. 363: 279:Moreover, in the preface of that text, he wrote: 267:perspective, similar sentiments were expressed by 481: 223:or pleasure, and perfectionism is distinct from 370:. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. 472:. Internet Archive. London, Smith, Elder. 178:, with chapters on a film, all but one ( 72:stated his conception of the good life ( 390: 237:imperium non paternale, sed patrioticum 482: 465: 415: 361: 231:regarded such a society as government 54:describes perfectionism as follows: 42:in obtaining the optimal quality of 13: 14: 511: 50:, physical, and material being. 352:. Oxford University Press, p. 3. 288: 459: 454:L'Anarchie et le Collectivisme 443: 434: 409: 384: 355: 342: 1: 490:Ethical schools and movements 335: 214: 7: 308: 10: 516: 63: 21:Perfectionism (psychology) 18: 391:Rothman, William (2014). 249:He wrote in this regard: 466:Arnold, Matthew (1889). 416:Cavell, Stanley (2005). 362:Cavell, Stanley (2005). 19:Not to be confused with 348:Hurka, Thomas (1993). 286: 261: 207:The Philadelphia Story 115:categorical imperative 61: 38:is the persistence of 281: 251: 195:It Happened One Night 56: 16:Philosophical concept 315:Christian perfection 190:comedy of remarriage 273:Culture and Anarchy 176:George Bernard Shaw 164:William Shakespeare 148:Friedrich Nietzsche 144:Ralph Waldo Emerson 301:imperative behind 99:Harvard University 507: 500:Ethical theories 474: 473: 463: 457: 447: 441: 438: 432: 431: 413: 407: 406: 388: 382: 381: 369: 359: 353: 346: 295:Mark Alan Walker 181:A Tale of Winter 152:John Stuart Mill 119:John Stuart Mill 85:The philosopher 515: 514: 510: 509: 508: 506: 505: 504: 480: 479: 478: 477: 464: 460: 448: 444: 439: 435: 428: 414: 410: 403: 389: 385: 378: 360: 356: 347: 343: 338: 311: 291: 217: 201:The Awful Truth 128:Cities of Words 66: 24: 17: 12: 11: 5: 513: 503: 502: 497: 492: 476: 475: 458: 450:Naquet, Alfred 442: 433: 426: 418:Cavell on Film 408: 401: 383: 376: 354: 340: 339: 337: 334: 333: 332: 330:Utilitarianism 327: 322: 317: 310: 307: 290: 287: 269:Matthew Arnold 225:utilitarianism 216: 213: 103:Stanley Cavell 101:in the 1980s, 87:Stanley Cavell 65: 62: 15: 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 512: 501: 498: 496: 493: 491: 488: 487: 485: 471: 470: 462: 455: 451: 446: 437: 429: 427:9780791464328 423: 419: 412: 404: 402:9780231166027 398: 394: 387: 379: 377:9780674013360 373: 368: 367: 358: 351: 350:Perfectionism 345: 341: 331: 328: 326: 323: 321: 318: 316: 313: 312: 306: 304: 303:transhumanism 300: 296: 289:Transhumanism 285: 280: 277: 274: 270: 266: 260: 257: 250: 247: 244: 243:Alfred Naquet 240: 238: 234: 230: 226: 222: 212: 209: 208: 203: 202: 197: 196: 191: 187: 183: 182: 177: 173: 169: 165: 161: 157: 156:Sigmund Freud 153: 149: 145: 141: 140:Immanuel Kant 137: 133: 129: 124: 120: 116: 112: 111:Immanuel Kant 108: 104: 100: 96: 91: 88: 83: 81: 80: 75: 71: 60: 55: 53: 49: 45: 41: 37: 36:perfectionism 33: 29: 22: 468: 461: 453: 445: 436: 417: 411: 392: 386: 365: 357: 349: 344: 293:Philosopher 292: 282: 278: 262: 252: 248: 241: 236: 218: 205: 199: 193: 179: 172:Henrik Ibsen 127: 94: 93:In his book 92: 84: 77: 67: 57: 52:Thomas Hurka 35: 32:value theory 25: 325:Rationalism 233:paternalism 186:Eric Rohmer 168:Henry James 123:utilitarian 495:Metaethics 484:Categories 336:References 320:Pragmatism 184:(1992) by 160:John Rawls 107:Emersonian 74:eudaimonia 276:light ". 256:Knowledge 221:happiness 215:Happiness 136:Aristotle 70:Aristotle 44:spiritual 452:(1904). 309:See also 265:critical 299:ethical 271:in his 263:From a 64:History 424:  399:  374:  48:mental 28:ethics 132:Plato 79:polis 422:ISBN 397:ISBN 372:ISBN 229:Kant 204:and 174:and 158:and 40:will 30:and 121:’s 26:In 486:: 305:. 198:, 170:, 166:, 154:, 150:, 146:, 142:, 138:, 134:, 46:, 34:, 456:. 430:. 405:. 380:. 23:.

Index

Perfectionism (psychology)
ethics
value theory
will
spiritual
mental
Thomas Hurka
Aristotle
eudaimonia
polis
Stanley Cavell
Harvard University
Stanley Cavell
Emersonian
Immanuel Kant
categorical imperative
John Stuart Mill
utilitarian
Plato
Aristotle
Immanuel Kant
Ralph Waldo Emerson
Friedrich Nietzsche
John Stuart Mill
Sigmund Freud
John Rawls
William Shakespeare
Henry James
Henrik Ibsen
George Bernard Shaw

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑