Knowledge

Proof calculus

Source đź“ť

115:, characterized by a certain style of formal inference, that may be specialized to produce specific formal systems, namely by specifying the actual inference rules for such a system. There is no consensus among logicians on how best to define the term. 94:
Usually a given proof calculus encompasses more than a single particular formal system, since many proof calculi are under-determined and can be used for radically different logics. For example, a paradigmatic case is the
91:
in a proof system is a set of axioms and rules of inference of proof system that infers that the well-formed formula is a theorem of proof system.
154: 301: 189:, readily admits formalisation. There is still some modern interest in syllogisms, carried out under the 276: 231:
Several systems have been proposed that replace the usual textual syntax with some graphical syntax.
384: 132: 123:
The most widely known proof calculi are those classical calculi that are still in widespread use:
243: 150: 291: 259: 216: 158: 379: 172:
Many other proof calculi were, or might have been, seminal, but are not widely used today.
104: 100: 8: 263: 88: 52: 306: 210: 62: 17: 327: 286: 236: 220: 146: 136: 56: 29: 165: 96: 205: 142: 108: 44: 349: 65:: List of rules that can be employed to prove theorems from axioms and theorems. 247: 128: 112: 373: 251: 200: 296: 255: 84: 180: 194: 281: 232: 176: 223:
easily might have been seminal, had history worked out differently.
185: 168:, which is the most studied formalism of structural proof theory. 76: 209:(1879) is usually regarded as introducing the modern concept of 68: 190: 111:. Thus, loosely speaking, a proof calculus is a template or 227:
Modern research in logic teems with rival proof calculi:
51:of formulas admitted by the system, for example, 371: 131:, of which the most famous example is the 1928 325: 118: 40:A proof system includes the components: 242:Recently, many logicians interested in 372: 153:, and which is the cornerstone of the 350:"Definition:Proof System - ProofWiki" 344: 342: 340: 203:'s two-dimensional notation of the 99:, which can be used to express the 13: 149:, which is the first formalism of 14: 396: 337: 155:formulae-as-types correspondence 319: 1: 312: 7: 302:Method of analytic tableaux 270: 246:have proposed calculi with 183:calculus, presented in the 35: 10: 401: 277:Propositional proof system 119:Examples of proof calculi 75:assumed to be valid. All 133:Hilbert–Ackermann system 79:are derived from axioms. 328:"General proof systems" 244:structural proof theory 239:are among such systems. 151:structural proof theory 292:Calculus of structures 260:calculus of structures 159:functional programming 101:consequence relations 105:intuitionistic logic 264:bunched implication 89:well-formed formula 53:propositional logic 326:Anita Wasilewska. 307:Resolution (logic) 157:relating logic to 63:Rules of inference 28:is built to prove 18:mathematical logic 287:Cirquent calculus 237:cirquent calculus 221:existential graph 147:natural deduction 137:first-order logic 57:first-order logic 392: 364: 363: 361: 360: 346: 335: 334: 332: 323: 166:sequent calculus 97:sequent calculus 400: 399: 395: 394: 393: 391: 390: 389: 385:Logical calculi 370: 369: 368: 367: 358: 356: 348: 347: 338: 330: 324: 320: 315: 273: 250:, for instance 206:Begriffsschrift 145:'s calculus of 143:Gerhard Gentzen 129:Hilbert systems 121: 109:relevance logic 45:Formal language 38: 12: 11: 5: 398: 388: 387: 382: 366: 365: 336: 317: 316: 314: 311: 310: 309: 304: 299: 294: 289: 284: 279: 272: 269: 268: 267: 248:deep inference 240: 225: 224: 214: 198: 170: 169: 162: 140: 120: 117: 113:design pattern 81: 80: 71:: Formulas in 66: 60: 37: 34: 22:proof calculus 9: 6: 4: 3: 2: 397: 386: 383: 381: 378: 377: 375: 355: 354:proofwiki.org 351: 345: 343: 341: 329: 322: 318: 308: 305: 303: 300: 298: 295: 293: 290: 288: 285: 283: 280: 278: 275: 274: 265: 261: 257: 256:hypersequents 253: 252:display logic 249: 245: 241: 238: 234: 230: 229: 228: 222: 218: 215: 212: 208: 207: 202: 201:Gottlob Frege 199: 196: 192: 188: 187: 182: 178: 175: 174: 173: 167: 163: 160: 156: 152: 148: 144: 141: 138: 134: 130: 127:The class of 126: 125: 124: 116: 114: 110: 106: 102: 98: 92: 90: 86: 78: 74: 70: 67: 64: 61: 58: 54: 50: 46: 43: 42: 41: 33: 31: 27: 23: 19: 380:Proof theory 357:. Retrieved 353: 321: 297:Formal proof 226: 204: 184: 171: 122: 93: 85:formal proof 82: 72: 48: 39: 26:proof system 25: 21: 15: 217:C.S. Peirce 181:syllogistic 374:Categories 359:2023-10-16 313:References 282:Proof nets 233:proof nets 211:quantifier 195:term logic 164:Gentzen's 47:: The set 30:statements 213:to logic. 177:Aristotle 271:See also 103:of both 77:theorems 36:Overview 186:Organon 262:, and 258:, the 69:Axioms 331:(PDF) 191:aegis 87:of a 24:or a 20:, a 235:and 179:'s 107:and 219:'s 193:of 135:of 55:or 16:In 376:: 352:. 339:^ 254:, 83:A 32:. 362:. 333:. 266:. 197:. 161:; 139:; 73:L 59:. 49:L

Index

mathematical logic
statements
Formal language
propositional logic
first-order logic
Rules of inference
Axioms
theorems
formal proof
well-formed formula
sequent calculus
consequence relations
intuitionistic logic
relevance logic
design pattern
Hilbert systems
Hilbert–Ackermann system
first-order logic
Gerhard Gentzen
natural deduction
structural proof theory
formulae-as-types correspondence
functional programming
sequent calculus
Aristotle
syllogistic
Organon
aegis
term logic
Gottlob Frege

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License. Additional terms may apply.

↑